PRADO, Circuit Judge:
This appeal concerns the constitutionality of 18 U.S.C. § 922(b)(1) and (c)(1), and attendant regulations, which prohibit federally licensed firearms dealers from selling handguns to persons under the age of 21. Appellants — the National Rifle Association and individuals who at the time of filing were over the age of 18 but under the age of 21 — brought suit in district court against several federal government agencies, challenging the constitutionality of the laws. The essence of their challenge is that the laws violate the Second Amendment and the equal protection component of the Fifth Amendment by preventing law-abiding 18-to-20-year-old adults from purchasing handguns from federally licensed dealers. The district court rejected their constitutional claims and granted summary judgment for the government. We AFFIRM.
Appellants filed suit in district court against the Bureau of Alcohol, Tobacco, Firearms, and Explosives ("ATF"), ATF's Acting Director, and the Attorney General of the United States, challenging the constitutionality of 18 U.S.C. §§ 922(b)(1) and (c)(1), as well as attendant regulations, 27 C.F.R. §§ 478.99(b)(1), 478.124(a), and 478.96(b). These provisions prohibit licensed dealers — i.e., federal firearms licensees ("FFLs") — from selling handguns to persons under the age of 21. Appellants include: (i) Andrew M. Payne, Rebekah Jennings, and Brennan Harmon, who were between the ages of 18 and 21 when the suit was filed; and (ii) the National Rifle Association ("NRA") on behalf of (a) 18-to-20-year-old members who are prevented from purchasing handguns from FFLs, and (b) FFL members who are prohibited from making such sales. Appellants asserted that the federal laws are unconstitutional because they infringe on the right of 18-to-20-year-old adults to keep and bear arms under the Second Amendment and deny them equal protection under the Due Process Clause of the Fifth Amendment. Appellants sought a declaratory judgment that the laws are unconstitutional, as well as injunctive relief.
Before the district court, the government filed a motion for summary judgment, arguing that Appellants lacked standing to challenge the federal laws and that their constitutional claims failed on the merits. The district court concluded that Appellants had standing, but then determined that Appellants failed to make out either a viable Second Amendment claim or a viable equal protection claim. Appellants timely appealed.
The federal laws at issue — 18 U.S.C. §§ 922(b)(1) and (c)(1), 27 C.F.R. §§ 478.99(b)(1), 478.124(a), and 478.96(b) — were enacted as part of the Omnibus Crime Control and Safe Streets Act of 1968, Pub.L. No. 90-351, 82 Stat. 197. Together, the laws regulate the sale of firearms by FFLs and are part of a larger statutory package that prohibits persons from "engag[ing] in the business of importing, manufacturing, or dealing in firearms," unless a person is a "licensed importer, licensed manufacturer, or licensed dealer." 18 U.S.C. § 922(a)(1)(A). To "engage[ ] in th[is] business" means to "devote[ ] time, attention, and labor" to the manufacture, sale, or importation of firearms or ammunition "as a regular course of trade or business with the principal objective of livelihood and profit through the repetitive purchase and resale of firearms." Id. § 921(21)(A)-(E).
The first contested provision, 18 U.S.C. § 922(b)(1), provides that:
This provision is paired with § 922(c)(1), which prevents an FFL from selling a firearm to a person "who does not appear in person at the licensee's business premises (other than another licensed importer, manufacturer, or dealer)" unless the person submits a sworn statement that "in the case of any firearm other than a shotgun or a rifle, [he or she is] twenty-one years or more of age."
These provisions are the statutory authority for several implementing regulations that Appellants also contest. First, 27 C.F.R. § 478.99(b)(1) provides that an FFL
Second, 27 C.F.R. §§ 478.96(b) and 478.124(a) prohibit FFLs from selling firearms unless they obtain a signed copy of Form 4473 from the purchaser. Form 4473 is used, among other purposes, to establish a purchaser's eligibility to possess a firearm by establishing his or her date of birth. Id. § 478.124(c)(1). It also requires the execution and dating of a sworn statement indicating that if "the firearm to be transferred is a firearm other than a shotgun or rifle, the transferee is 21 years or more of age." Id. § 478.124(f).
Congress later supplemented this regulatory scheme with the Violent Crime Control and Law Enforcement Act of 1994, which prohibits persons under the age of 18 from possessing handguns and bars the transfer of handguns to them, with limited exceptions. Pub.L. No. 103-322, § 110201, 108 Stat. 1796, 2010 (adding 18 U.S.C. § 922(x)). The parties agree that the network of federal laws amounts to the following. Eighteen-to-twenty-year-olds may possess and use handguns. Parents or guardians may gift handguns to 18-to-20-year-olds.
We review questions of standing de novo. Time Warner Cable, Inc. v. Hudson, 667 F.3d 630, 635 (5th Cir.2012). The parties seeking access to federal court bear the burden of establishing their standing. Id. "[T]he irreducible constitutional minimum of standing contains three elements." Lujan v. Defenders of Wildlife, 504 U.S. 555, 560, 112 S.Ct. 2130, 119 L.Ed.2d 351 (1992). The first is an "injury in fact," which is a "concrete and particularized... invasion of a legally protected
"While the proof required to establish standing increases as the suit proceeds, the standing inquiry remains focused on whether the party invoking jurisdiction had the requisite stake in the outcome when the suit was filed." Davis v. Fed. Election Comm'n, 554 U.S. 724, 734, 128 S.Ct. 2759, 171 L.Ed.2d 737 (2008) (citations omitted). Mootness, however, is "the doctrine of standing set in a time frame: The requisite personal interest that must exist at the commencement of the litigation (standing) must continue throughout its existence (mootness)." U.S. Parole Comm'n v. Geraghty, 445 U.S. 388, 397, 100 S.Ct. 1202, 63 L.Ed.2d 479 (1980) (citation omitted). When "named plaintiffs will not benefit from a favorable ruling on the question implicating injunctive relief, we hold that th[e] question is moot as to them." Pederson v. La. State Univ., 213 F.3d 858, 874 (5th Cir.2000).
Under the doctrine of associational standing, an association may have standing to bring suit on behalf of its members when:
Ass'n of Am. Physicians & Surgeons, Inc. v. Tex. Med. Bd., 627 F.3d 547, 550 (5th Cir.2010) (citation omitted). The first prong requires that at least one member of the association have standing to sue in his or her own right. Tex. Democratic Party v. Benkiser, 459 F.3d 582, 587-88 (5th Cir.2006).
Before oral argument in this case, counsel for Appellants notified us that Rebekah Jennings and Brendan Harmon had turned 21. Because they have aged out of the demographic group affected by the ban at bar, the issues on appeal are moot as to them. See Pederson, 213 F.3d at 874. Andrew Payne, the third individual Appellant, will remain under the age of 21 throughout the appeal. Mootness does not affect his claim. In addition, the NRA has asserted associational standing on behalf of its members who are between the ages of 18 and 21. The NRA submitted a sworn declaration that it had over 11,000 members who would be covered by the ban, and NRA members between the ages of 18 and 21 submitted sworn declarations that they cannot purchase handguns from FFLs because of the ban. However, the government contends that Payne and the NRA's under-21 members have not suffered an injury-in-fact.
We disagree and hold that Payne and the NRA, on behalf of its under-21 members, have standing to bring this suit. The government is correct that the challenged federal laws do not bar 18-to-20-year-olds from possessing or using handguns. The laws also do not bar 18-to-20-year-olds from receiving handguns from parents or guardians. Yet, by prohibiting FFLs from selling handguns to 18-to-20-year-olds, the laws cause those persons a
Standing may be satisfied by the presence of "at least one individual plaintiff who has demonstrated standing to assert the[ ] [contested] rights as his own." Vill. of Arlington Heights v. Metro. Hous. Dev. Corp., 429 U.S. 252, 264, 97 S.Ct. 555, 50 L.Ed.2d 450 (1977); see also Horne v. Flores, 557 U.S. 433, 446-47, 129 S.Ct. 2579, 174 L.Ed.2d 406 (2009). Having established Payne's standing and the NRA's associational standing on behalf of its 18-to-20-year-olds members, we need not discuss the NRA's associational standing on behalf of its FFL members. We therefore proceed to the merits of this appeal.
The crux of Appellants' position on the merits is that the federal ban at bar violates their rights under the Second Amendment, given the holding in District of Columbia v. Heller, 554 U.S. 570, 128 S.Ct. 2783, 171 L.Ed.2d 637 (2008). Appellants urge that, by preventing an 18-to-20-year-old from purchasing handguns from FFLs, the laws impermissibly infringe on that individual's right under the Second Amendment to keep and bear arms. The district court granted summary judgment for the government, rejecting the Second Amendment claim. We review the constitutionality of federal statutes de novo. United States v. Portillo-Munoz, 643 F.3d 437, 439 (5th Cir.2011).
No other circuit court has considered the constitutionality of the challenged federal laws in light of Heller. Only a single district court has considered the constitutionality of the ban, upholding it under intermediate scrutiny. See United States v. Bledsoe, No. SA-08-CR-13(2)-XR, 2008 WL 3538717, at *4 (W.D.Tex. Aug. 8, 2008). We affirmed the defendant's conviction in that case without reaching the constitutional issue. See United States v. Bledsoe, 334 Fed.Appx. 711 (5th Cir.2009) (unpublished). Consequently, this is an issue of first impression in this circuit. Because we — unlike some of our fellow circuit courts — have yet to establish a framework for evaluating post-Heller Second Amendment challenges, we sketch a framework here.
The Second Amendment provides: "A well regulated Militia, being necessary to the security of a free State, the right of the people to keep and bear Arms, shall not be infringed." In Heller, the Supreme Court made clear that the Second Amendment
The precise question before the Court in Heller was whether Washington, D.C. statutes banning the possession of usable handguns in the home — in addition to requiring residents to keep their firearms either disassembled or trigger locked — violated the Second Amendment. 554 U.S. at 573-75, 128 S.Ct. 2783. The Court invalidated the laws because they violated the central right that the Second Amendment was intended to protect — that is, the "right of law-abiding, responsible citizens to use arms in defense of hearth and home." Id. at 635, 128 S.Ct. 2783 (emphasis added); see also id. at 628-30, 128 S.Ct. 2783 (distilling the Second Amendment to its "core" interest of "self-defense" and the "protection of one's home and family"). Indeed, the ban on home handgun possession squarely struck the core of the Second Amendment — a rare feat, as the Court observed that "[f]ew laws in the history of our Nation have come close to the severe restriction of the District's handgun ban." Id. at 629, 128 S.Ct. 2783. The Court thus noted that the ban "would fail constitutional muster" under "any of the standards of scrutiny" applicable to "enumerated constitutional rights." Id. at 628-29, 128 S.Ct. 2783.
In a critical passage, moreover, the Court emphasized that the "right secured by the Second Amendment is not unlimited." Id. at 626, 128 S.Ct. 2783. As the Court explained:
Id. at 626-27, 128 S.Ct. 2783 (emphases added) (citations omitted). The Court hastened to add that it had listed "these presumptively lawful regulatory measures only as examples"; the list was illustrative, "not exhaustive." Id. at 627 n. 26, 128 S.Ct. 2783.
Understandably, the Court did not undertake an "exhaustive historical analysis... of the full scope of the Second Amendment." Id. at 626, 128 S.Ct. 2783; see also id. at 635, 128 S.Ct. 2783 ("[T]here will be
But our fellow courts of appeals have filled the analytical vacuum. A two-step inquiry has emerged as the prevailing approach: the first step is to determine whether the challenged law impinges upon a right protected by the Second Amendment — that is, whether the law regulates conduct that falls within the scope of the Second Amendment's guarantee; the second step is to determine whether to apply intermediate or strict scrutiny to the law, and then to determine whether the law survives the proper level of scrutiny. See United States v. Greeno, 679 F.3d 510, 518 (6th Cir.2012); Heller v. District of Columbia, 670 F.3d 1244, 1252 (D.C.Cir.2011) (Heller II); Ezell v. City of Chicago, 651 F.3d 684, 701-04 (7th Cir.2011); United States v. Chester, 628 F.3d 673, 680 (4th Cir.2010); United States v. Reese, 627 F.3d 792, 800-01 (10th Cir.2010) United States v. Marzzarella, 614 F.3d 85, 89 (3d Cir.2010). But see United States v. Skoien, 614 F.3d 638, 641-42 (7th Cir.2010) (en banc) (eschewing the two-step framework and resisting the "levels of scrutiny quagmire," but applying intermediate scrutiny to a categorical restriction). We adopt a version of this two-step approach and sketch a skeleton of the framework here, leaving future cases to put meat on the bones.
We agree that the first inquiry is whether the conduct at issue falls within the scope of the Second Amendment right. See, e.g., Chester, 628 F.3d at 680. To determine whether a law impinges on the Second Amendment right, we look to whether the law harmonizes with the historical traditions associated with the Second Amendment guarantee. See Heller, 554 U.S. at 577-628, 128 S.Ct. 2783 (interpreting Second Amendment based on historical traditions); United States v. Masciandaro, 638 F.3d 458, 470 (4th Cir.2011) ("[H]istorical meaning enjoys a privileged interpretive role in the Second Amendment context."). Heller illustrates that we may rely on a wide array of interpretive materials to conduct a historical analysis. See 554 U.S. at 600-26, 128 S.Ct. 2783 (relying on courts, legislators, and scholars from before ratification through the late 19th century to interpret the Second Amendment); see also United States v. Rene E., 583 F.3d 8, 13-16 (1st Cir.2009) (relying on wide-ranging materials, including late 19th- and early 20th-century cases, to uphold federal ban on juvenile handgun possession).
We agree with the prevailing view that the appropriate level of scrutiny "depends on the nature of the conduct being regulated and the degree to which the challenged law burdens the right." See Chester, 628 F.3d at 682 (observing that a "severe burden on the core Second Amendment right of armed self-defense should require a strong justification," but "less severe burdens on the right" and "laws that do not implicate the central self-defense concern of the Second Amendment[ ] may be more easily justified" (quotation and citation omitted)); accord Heller II, 670 F.3d at 1257 ("[A] regulation that imposes a substantial burden upon the core right of self-defense protected by the Second Amendment must have a strong justification, whereas a regulation that imposes a less substantial burden should be proportionately easier to justify."); Masciandaro, 638 F.3d at 470 (observing that the analysis turns on "the character of the Second Amendment question presented" — that is, "the nature of a person's Second Amendment interest [and] the extent to which those interests are burdened by government regulation"). A regulation that threatens a right at the core of the Second Amendment — for example, the right of a law-abiding, responsible adult to possess and use a handgun to defend his or her home and family, see Heller, 554 U.S. at 635, 128 S.Ct. 2783 — triggers strict scrutiny. See Heller II, 670 F.3d at 1257; Masciandaro, 638 F.3d at 470; Chester, 628 F.3d at 682. A less severe regulation — a regulation that does not encroach on the core of the Second Amendment — requires a less demanding means-ends showing. See Heller II, 670 F.3d at 1257; Masciandaro, 638 F.3d at 470; Chester, 628 F.3d at 682. This more lenient level of scrutiny could be called "intermediate" scrutiny, but regardless of the label, this level requires the government to demonstrate a "reasonable fit" between the challenged regulation and an "important" government objective. See Marzzarella, 614 F.3d at 98; accord Chester, 628 F.3d at 683; see also Masciandaro, 638 F.3d at 471 (stating that intermediate scrutiny requires government to demonstrate that the regulation is "reasonably adapted to a substantial governmental interest"). This "intermediate" scrutiny test must be more rigorous than rational basis review, which Heller held "could not be used to evaluate the extent to which a legislature may regulate a specific, enumerated right" such as "the right to keep and bear arms." See 554 U.S. at 628 n. 27, 128 S.Ct. 2783; see also id. ("If all that was required to overcome the right to keep and bear arms was a rational basis, the Second Amendment would be redundant with the separate constitutional
We admit that it is difficult to map Heller's "longstanding," id. at 626, 128 S.Ct. 2783, "presumptively lawful regulatory measures," id. at 627 n. 26, 128 S.Ct. 2783, onto this two-step framework. It is difficult to discern whether "longstanding prohibitions on the possession of firearms by felons and the mentally ill, ... or laws imposing conditions and qualifications on the commercial sale of arms," id. at 626-27, 128 S.Ct. 2783, by virtue of their presumptive validity, either (i) presumptively fail to burden conduct protected by the Second Amendment, or (ii) presumptively trigger and pass constitutional muster under a lenient level of scrutiny. See, e.g., Marzzarella, 614 F.3d at 91 (recognizing that the designation — longstanding, presumptively lawful measure — is ambiguous). For now, we state that a longstanding, presumptively lawful regulatory measure — whether or not it is specified on Heller's illustrative list — would likely fall outside the ambit of the Second Amendment; that is, such a measure would likely be upheld at step one of our framework. See Heller II, 670 F.3d at 1253 ("[A] regulation that is `longstanding,' which necessarily means it has long been accepted by the public, is not likely to burden a constitutional right; concomitantly the activities covered by a longstanding regulation are presumptively not protected from regulation by the Second Amendment.").
In addition, Heller demonstrates that a regulation can be deemed "longstanding" even if it cannot boast a precise foundingera analogue. See Skoien, 614 F.3d at 640-41 ("[W]e do take from Heller the message that exclusions need not mirror limits that were on the books in 1791."); cf. Heller II, 670 F.3d at 1253-54 (relying on early 20th-century state statutes to show that D.C. handgun registration requirement was "longstanding" and did not "impinge upon the right protected by the Second Amendment"). After all, Heller considered firearm possession bans on felons and the mentally ill to be longstanding, yet the current versions of these bans are of mid-20th century vintage. See Booker, 644 F.3d at 23-24 (explaining that the federal felony firearm possession ban, 18 U.S.C. § 922(g)(1), "bears little resemblance to laws in effect at the time the Second Amendment was ratified," as it was not enacted until 1938, was not expanded to cover non-violent felonies until 1961, and was not re-focused from receipt to possession until 1968); Skoien, 614 F.3d at 640-41 (explaining that 18 U.S.C. § 922(g)(4), which forbids firearm possession by a person who has been adjudicated
Having sketched our two-step analytical framework, we must emphasize that we are persuaded to adopt this framework because it comports with the language of Heller. As for step one, Heller itself suggests that the threshold issue is whether the party is entitled to the Second Amendment's protection. See 554 U.S. at 635, 128 S.Ct. 2783 ("Assuming that Heller is not disqualified from the exercise of Second Amendment rights, the District must permit him to register his handgun ...."); see also id. at 626-27, 128 S.Ct. 2783 (providing a non-exhaustive list of longstanding, presumptively lawful regulatory measures). As for step two, by taking rational basis review off the table, and by faulting a dissenting opinion for proposing an interest-balancing inquiry rather than a traditional level of scrutiny, the Court's language suggests that intermediate and strict scrutiny are on the table. See id. at 628 n. 27, 128 S.Ct. 2783; id. at 634, 128 S.Ct. 2783 ("[Justice Breyer] proposes ... none of the traditionally expressed levels (strict scrutiny, intermediate scrutiny, rational basis), but rather a judge-empowering `interest-balancing inquiry' ...." (emphasis added) (quoting id. at 689, 128 S.Ct. 2783 (Breyer, J., dissenting))). The Court's use of the word "rather" demonstrates that, in the Court's view, the familiar scrutiny tests are not equivalent to interest balancing. In rejecting Justice Breyer's proposed interest-balancing inquiry, we understand the Court to have distinguished that inquiry from the traditional levels of scrutiny; we do not understand the Court to have rejected all heightened scrutiny analysis. But see Heller II, 670 F.3d at 1277-78 (Kavanaugh, J., dissenting) (arguing that the Heller Court's rejection of Justice Breyer's interest-balancing inquiry amounted to a rejection of all balancing tests).
Furthermore, we are persuaded to adopt the two-step framework outlined above because First Amendment doctrine informs it. See Marzzarella, 614 F.3d at 89 n. 4 (looking toward the First Amendment for guidance in interpreting the Second Amendment and observing that "Heller itself repeatedly invokes the First Amendment in establishing principles governing the Second Amendment"). First, First Amendment doctrine supports commencing our analysis with a threshold inquiry into whether the Second Amendment protects the conduct at issue. Similar to the first step of our Second Amendment framework, the first step in analyzing a First Amendment challenge is to determine whether the conduct (i.e., speech) in question is protected. See Ashcroft v. Free Speech Coal., 535 U.S. 234, 245-46, 122 S.Ct. 1389, 152 L.Ed.2d 403 (2002) ("The freedom of speech has its limits; it
Before we apply the framework described above to the challenged federal laws, we place them in context. Congress passed the Omnibus Crime Control and Safe Streets Act of 1968 following a multi-year inquiry into violent crime that included "field investigation and public hearings." S.Rep. No. 88-1340, at 1 (1964). According to the preamble to the Act, Congress had found "that there is a widespread traffic in firearms moving in or otherwise affecting interstate or foreign commerce, and that the existing Federal controls over such traffic do not adequately enable the States to control this traffic within their own borders through the exercise of their police power." Pub.L. No. 90-351, § 901(a)(1), 82 Stat. 197, 225 (1968). The preamble further declares:
Id. § 901(a)(2), 82 Stat. at 225; see also Huddleston v. United States, 415 U.S. 814, 824, 94 S.Ct. 1262, 39 L.Ed.2d 782 (1974) (stating that the purpose of the 1968 Act was to curb crime by keeping "firearms out of the hands of those not legally entitled to possess them because of age, criminal background, or incompetency" (quoting S.Rep. No. 90-1501, at 22 (1968))).
Moreover, in a section titled "Acquisition of firearms by juveniles and minors,"
S. Rep. No. 90-1097, at 79 (1968), 1968 U.S.C.C.A.N. 2112, 2167.
Congress's investigation confirmed a "causal relationship between the easy availability of firearms other than a rifle or a shotgun and ... youthful criminal behavior." Pub.L. No. 90-351, § 901(a)(6), 82 Stat. at 225-26; see also Federal Firearms Act: Hearings Before the Subcomm. to Investigate Juvenile Delinquency of the Sen. Comm. on the Judiciary, 90th Cong. 57 (1967) (testimony of Sheldon S. Cohen) ("The greatest growth of crime today is in the area of young people .... The easy availability of weapons makes their tendency toward wild, and sometimes irrational behavior that much more violent, that much more deadly."). Having found that concealable firearms had been "widely sold by federally licensed importers and dealers to emotionally immature, or thrill-bent juveniles and minors prone to criminal behavior," Pub.L. No. 90-351, § 901(a)(6), 82 Stat. at 226, Congress concluded that "only through adequate Federal control over interstate and foreign commerce in these weapons, and over all persons engaging in the business of importing, manufacturing, or dealing in them, can this grave problem be properly dealt with, and effective State and local regulation of this traffic be made possible," id. § 901(a)(3), 82 Stat. at 225.
The legislative record makes clear that Congress's purpose in preventing persons under 21 — including 18-to-20-year-olds — from purchasing handguns from FFLs was to curb violent crime. Essentially, then, the federal laws at issue are safety-driven, age-based categorical restrictions on handgun access.
Having placed the challenged federal laws in their proper context, we now consider
As the Supreme Court recognized in Heller, the right to keep and bear arms has never been unlimited. 554 U.S. at 626, 128 S.Ct. 2783; see also Robertson v. Baldwin, 165 U.S. 275, 281, 17 S.Ct. 326, 41 L.Ed. 715 (1897) (observing that the right to keep and bear arms, like other rights "inherited from our English ancestors" and protected by the Bill of Rights, has "from time immemorial, been subject to certain well-recognized exceptions, arising from the necessities of the case"). Since even before the Revolution, gun use and gun control have been inextricably intertwined. The historical record shows that gun safety regulation was commonplace in the colonies, and around the time of the founding, a variety of gun safety regulations were on the books; these included safety laws regulating the storage of gun powder, laws keeping track of who in the community had guns, laws administering gun use in the context of militia service (including laws requiring militia members to attend "musters," public gatherings where officials would inspect and account for guns), laws prohibiting the use of firearms on certain occasions and in certain places, and laws disarming certain groups and restricting sales to certain groups. See Adam Winkler, Gunfight: The Battle over the Right to Bear Arms in America 113-18 (2011); Saul Cornell & Nathan DeDino, A Well Regulated Right: The Early American Origins of Gun Control, 73 Fordham L.Rev. 487, 502-13 (2004). It appears that when the fledgling republic adopted the Second Amendment, an expectation of sensible gun safety regulation was woven into the tapestry of the guarantee.
Noteworthy among these revolutionary and founding-era gun regulations are those that targeted particular groups for public safety reasons. For example, several jurisdictions passed laws that confiscated weapons owned by persons who refused to swear an oath of allegiance to the state or to the nation. See Cornell & DeDino, 73 Fordham L.Rev. at 507-08. Although these Loyalists were neither criminals nor traitors, American legislators had determined that permitting these persons to keep and bear arms posed a potential danger. Id. ("The law demonstrates that in a well regulated society, the state could disarm those it deemed likely to disrupt society."); see also Winkler, Gunfight, at 116 (concluding that "[t]he founders didn't think government should have the power to take away everyone's guns, but they were perfectly willing to confiscate weapons from anyone deemed untrustworthy," a group that included law-abiding slaves, free blacks, and Loyalists); Don B. Kates & Clayton E. Cramer, Second Amendment Limitations and Criminological Considerations, 60 Hastings L.J. 1339, 1360 (2009) ("[F]rom time immemorial, various jurisdictions recognizing a right to arms have nevertheless taken the step of forbidding suspect groups from having arms. American legislators at the time of the Bill of Rights seem to have been aware of this tradition ...." (footnote omitted)).
In the view of at least some members of the founding generation, disarming select groups for the sake of public safety was compatible with the right to arms specifically and with the idea of liberty generally. See Saul Cornell, Commonplace or Anachronism: The Standard Model, the Second Amendment, and the Problem of History in Contemporary Constitutional Theory, 16 Const. Comment. 221, 231-36
These categorical restrictions may have been animated by a classical republican notion that only those with adequate civic "virtue" could claim the right to arms. Scholars have proposed that at the time of the founding, "the right to arms was inextricably and multifariously linked to that of civic virtu (i.e., the virtuous citizenry)," and that "[o]ne implication of this emphasis on the virtuous citizen is that the right to arms does not preclude laws disarming the unvirtuous citizens (i.e., criminals) or those who, like children or the mentally imbalanced, are deemed incapable of virtue." Kates & Cramer, 60 Hastings L.J. at 1359-60.
Notably, the term "minor" or "infant" — as those terms were historically understood — applied to persons under the age of 21, not only to persons under the age of 18. The age of majority at common law was 21, and it was not until the 1970s that States enacted legislation to lower the age of majority to 18. See, e.g., Black's Law Dictionary 847 (9th ed. 2009) ("An infant in the eyes of the law is a person under the age of twenty-one years, and at that period... he or she is said to attain majority...." (quoting John Indermaur, Principles of the Common Law 195 (Edmund H. Bennett ed., 1st Am. ed. 1878))); id. ("The common-law rule provided that a person was an infant until he reached the age of twenty-one. The rule continues at the present time, though by statute in some jurisdictions the age may be lower." (quoting John Edward Murray Jr., Murray on
Arms-control legislation intensified through the 1800s, see Cornell & DeDino, 73 Fordham L.Rev. at 512-13, and by the end of the 19th century, nineteen States and the District of Columbia had enacted laws expressly restricting the ability of persons under 21 to purchase or use particular firearms, or restricting the ability of "minors" to purchase or use particular firearms while the state age of majority was set at age 21.
Meanwhile, "19th-century courts and commentators," Heller, 554 U.S. at 603, 128 S.Ct. 2783, maintained that age-based restrictions on the purchase of firearms —
In the 1878 case that Cooley referenced, the Tennessee Supreme Court upheld a conviction under a state law making it a misdemeanor to sell, give, or loan a pistol to a minor, Callicutt, 69 Tenn. at 714-15, when the age of majority was set at 21. The defendant argued that the law violated the state's Second Amendment analogue, reasoning that because "every citizen who is subject to military duty has the right `to keep and bear arms,' ... this right necessarily implies the right to buy or otherwise acquire, and the right in others to give, sell, or loan to him." Id. at 716. In rejecting the defendant's challenge, the court explained that the "wise and salutary" legislation was passed to "prevent crime" and suppress "the pernicious and dangerous practice of carrying arms," and was not "intended to affect, and [did] not in fact abridge," the right to keep and bear arms. Id. at 715-17. Likewise, in Coleman v. State, 32 Ala. 581, 582-83 (1858), the Alabama Supreme Court upheld a conviction for violating a state law making it a misdemeanor to sell, give, or lend a pistol to a male minor, when the age of majority was set at 21.
We have summarized considerable evidence that burdening the conduct at issue — the ability of 18-to-20-year-olds to purchase handguns from FFLs — is consistent with a longstanding, historical tradition, which suggests that the conduct at issue falls outside the Second Amendment's protection. At a high level of generality, the present ban is consistent with a longstanding tradition of targeting select groups' ability to access and to use arms for the sake of public safety. See Winkler, Gunfight, at 116; Cornell & DeDino, 73 Fordham L.Rev. at 507-08. More specifically, the present ban appears consistent with a longstanding tradition of age- and safety-based restrictions on the ability to access arms. In conformity with founding-era thinking, and in conformity with the views of various 19th-century legislators and courts, Congress restricted the ability of minors under 21 to purchase handguns because Congress found that they tend to be relatively immature and that denying them easy access to handguns would deter violent crime. Compare Kates & Cramer, 60 Hastings L.J. at 1360 (reflecting founding-era attitude that minors were inadequately virtuous to keep and bear arms), and Callicutt, 69 Tenn. at 716-17 (referring to prohibition on firearm sales to minors as "wise and salutary" legislation designed to "prevent crime"), with Pub.L. No. 90-351, § 901(a)(6), 82 Stat. 197, 226 (1968) (reflecting concern that handguns had been "widely sold by [FFLs] to emotionally immature, or thrill-bent juveniles and minors prone to criminal behavior").
This reasoning finds support in United States v. Rene E., in which the First Circuit canvassed sources similar to ours and upheld the constitutionality of 18 U.S.C. § 922(x), which prohibits persons under age 18 from possessing handguns and prohibits
To be sure, we are unable to divine the Founders' specific views on whether 18-to-20-year-olds had a stronger claim than 17-year-olds to the Second Amendment guarantee. The Founders may not even have shared a collective view on such a subtle and fine-grained distinction. The important point is that there is considerable historical evidence of age- and safety-based restrictions on the ability to access arms. Modern restrictions on the ability of persons under 21 to purchase handguns — and the ability of persons under 18 to possess handguns — seem, to us, to be firmly historically rooted.
Nonetheless, we face institutional challenges in conducting a definitive review of the relevant historical record. Although we are inclined to uphold the challenged federal laws at step one of our analytical framework, in an abundance of caution, we proceed to step two. We ultimately conclude that the challenged federal laws pass constitutional muster even if they implicate the Second Amendment guarantee.
Assuming that the challenged federal laws burden conduct within the scope of the Second Amendment, we must evaluate the laws under a suitable standard of constitutional scrutiny. A law that burdens the core of the Second Amendment guarantee — for example, "the right of law-abiding, responsible citizens to use arms in defense of hearth and home," Heller, 554 U.S. at 635, 128 S.Ct. 2783 — would trigger strict scrutiny, while a less severe law would be proportionately easier to justify. See Heller II, 670 F.3d at 1257; Masciandaro, 638 F.3d at 470; Chester, 628 F.3d at 682. The latter, "intermediate" standard of scrutiny requires the government to show a reasonable fit between the law and an important government objective.
Unquestionably, the challenged federal laws trigger nothing more than "intermediate" scrutiny. We have demonstrated that this federal scheme is not a salient outlier in the historical landscape of gun control. And unlike the D.C. ban in Heller, this ban does not disarm an entire community, but instead prohibits commercial handgun sales to 18-to-20-year-olds — a discrete category. The narrow ambit of the ban's target militates against strict scrutiny.
Indeed, Heller's observation that longstanding prohibitions on firearm possession by felons and the mentally ill are presumptively valid, 554 U.S. at 626, 627 n. 26, 128 S.Ct. 2783, entails that the Second Amendment permits "categorical regulation of gun possession by classes of persons." Booker, 644 F.3d at 23; see also Skoien, 614 F.3d at 640, 641 (inferring from Heller that "statutory prohibitions on the possession of weapons by some persons are proper" and noting that "[c]ategorical limits on the possession of firearms would not be a constitutional anomaly"). Like the federal bans targeting felons and the mentally ill, the federal laws targeting minors under 21 are an outgrowth of an American tradition of regulating certain groups' access to arms for the sake of public safety. Compare Kates & Cramer, 60 Hastings L.J. at 1360 (arguing that the founding generation sought to disarm the unvirtuous, including minor children, felons, and the mentally ill), with S.Rep. No. 90-1501, at 22 (1968) (stating that the purpose of the 1968 Act was to curb crime by keeping "firearms out of the hands of those not legally entitled to possess them because of age, criminal background or
Moreover, as with felons and the mentally ill, categorically restricting the presumptive Second Amendment rights of 18-to-20-year-olds does not violate the central concern of the Second Amendment. The Second Amendment, at its core, protects "law-abiding, responsible" citizens. See Heller, 554 U.S. at 635, 128 S.Ct. 2783 (emphasis added). Congress found that persons under 21 tend to be relatively irresponsible and can be prone to violent crime, especially when they have easy access to handguns. See Pub.L. No. 90-351, § 901(a)(6), 82 Stat. at 197, 225 (1968) (referring to "emotionally immature, or thrill-bent juveniles and minors prone to criminal behavior"); cf. Chester, 628 F.3d at 682-83 (applying intermediate scrutiny to 18 U.S.C. § 922(g)(9), the federal domestic-violence-misdemeanant firearm possession ban, and holding that misdemeanant-plaintiff's claimed "right to possess a firearm in his home for the purpose of self-defense" was "not within the core right identified in Heller — the right of a law-abiding, responsible citizen to possess and carry a weapon for self-defense").
Granted, 18-to-20-year-olds may have a stronger claim to the Second Amendment guarantee than convicted felons and domestic-violence misdemeanants have. Culpable criminal conduct has not put 18-to-20-year-olds in the cross-hairs of the ban at bar. Still, unlike bans on felons, the mentally ill, and domestic-violence misdemeanants, this ban does not severely burden the presumptive Second Amendment rights of the targeted class's members. While the former bans extinguish the Second Amendment rights of the class members by totally preventing them from possessing firearms, this ban is not so extreme.
First, these federal laws do not severely burden the Second Amendment rights of 18-to-20-year-olds because they impose an age qualification on commercial firearm sales: FFLs may not sell handguns to persons under the age of 21. Far from a total prohibition on handgun possession and use, these laws resemble "laws imposing conditions and qualifications on the commercial sale of arms," which Heller deemed "presumptively lawful." See 554 U.S. at 626-27 & n. 26, 128 S.Ct. 2783. It is not clear that the Court had an age qualification in mind when it penned that sentence, but to the extent that these laws resemble presumptively lawful regulatory measures, they must not trigger strict scrutiny.
Second, these laws do not strike the core of the Second Amendment because they do not prevent 18-to-20-year-olds from possessing and using handguns "in defense of hearth and home." See id. at 628-30, 635, 128 S.Ct. 2783; cf. Heller II, 670 F.3d at 1255-58 (applying intermediate scrutiny to D.C. registration requirements that "make it considerably more difficult for a person lawfully to acquire and keep a firearm, including a handgun, for the purpose of self-defense in the home — the `core lawful purpose' protected by the Second Amendment," but that do not "prevent[] an individual from possessing a firearm in his home or elsewhere, whether for self-defense or hunting, or any other lawful purpose"). Under this federal regulatory
Third, these laws demand only an "intermediate" level of scrutiny because they regulate commercial sales through an age qualification with temporary effect. Any 18-to-20-year-old subject to the ban will soon grow up and out of its reach. It is useful to compare this case with United States v. Yancey, in which the Seventh Circuit held that 18 U.S.C. § 922(g)(3), the illegal-drug-user firearm possession ban, was "far less onerous" than the firearm-possession bans on felons and the mentally ill because "unlike those who have been convicted of a felony or committed to a mental institution and so face a lifetime ban, an unlawful drug user like [the defendant] could regain his right to possess a firearm simply by ending his drug abuse." 621 F.3d 681, 686-87 (7th Cir.2010). Similar logic applies here. The temporary nature of the burden reduces its severity. Consequently, we hold that these laws deserve what we have dubbed an "intermediate" level of scrutiny.
In applying "intermediate" scrutiny, we determine whether there is a reasonable fit between the law and an important government objective; that is, the government must show that the law is reasonably adapted to an important government interest. See Marzzarella, 614 F.3d at 98; accord Chester, 628 F.3d at 683; see also Masciandaro, 638 F.3d at 470. We conclude that the challenged ban passes constitutional muster under "intermediate" scrutiny.
The government has put forth evidence that, through the 1968 Act, Congress sought to manage an important public safety problem: the ease with which young persons — including 18-to-20-year-olds — were getting their hands on handguns through FFLs. As discussed supra, Section III.B, Congress conducted a multi-year investigation that revealed a causal relationship between the easy availability of firearms to young people under 21 and the rise in crime. See Pub.L. No. 90-351, § 901(a)(6), 82 Stat. 197, 225-26 (1968) (identifying a "causal relationship between the easy availability of firearms other than a rifle or shotgun and juvenile and youthful criminal behavior"); id. § 901(a)(2), 82 Stat. at 225 (identifying "ease with which" young persons could "acquire firearms other than a rifle or shotgun" as a "significant factor in the prevalence of lawlessness and violent crime in the United States"). Indeed, at a hearing held in connection with Congress's inquiry, a law enforcement official reported, "The greatest growth of crime today is in the area of young people, juveniles, and young adults. The easy availability of weapons makes their tendency toward wild, and sometimes irrational behavior that much more violent, that much more deadly." Federal Firearms Act: Hearings Before the Subcomm. to Investigate Juvenile Delinquency of the Sen. Comm. on the Judiciary, 90th Cong. 57 (1967) (testimony of Sheldon S. Cohen).
The legislative record illustrates that Congress was concerned not only with "juveniles" under the age of 18, but also with "minors" under the age of 21. See S.Rep. No. 90-1097, at 79 (1968), 1968 U.S.C.C.A.N. 2112, at 2167 ("The clandestine acquisition of firearms by juveniles and minors is a most serious problem facing law enforcement and the citizens of
The legislative record also demonstrates that Congress was particularly concerned with the FFL's role in the crime problem. The investigation had revealed that FFLs constituted the central conduit of handgun traffic to young persons. See Federal Firearms Act: Hearings Before the Subcomm. to Investigate Juvenile Delinquency of the Sen. Comm. on the Judiciary, 89th Cong. 67 (1965) (testimony of Sheldon S. Cohen) ("The vast majority, in fact, almost all of these firearms, are put into the hands of juveniles by importers, manufacturers, and dealers who operate under licenses issued by the Federal Government.... The way to end this dangerous practice is to stop these federal licensees from selling firearms to juveniles and this is one of the major things that [the proposed legislation] would do."); Pub.L. No. 90-351, § 901(a)(6), 82 Stat. at 226 (finding that concealable firearms had been "widely sold by federally licensed importers and dealers to emotionally immature, or thrill-bent juveniles and minors prone to criminal behavior"); id. § 901(a)(3), 82 Stat. at 225 (concluding that "only through adequate Federal control over interstate and foreign commerce in these weapons, and over all persons engaging in the business of importing, manufacturing, or dealing in them, can this grave problem be properly dealt with, and effective State and local regulation of this traffic be made possible").
Additionally, the legislative record reflects Congress's concern with the "particular type of weapon that is predominantly used by the criminal" and that is "principally used in the commission of serious crime" — i.e., the "handgun." S.Rep. No. 89-1866, at 4-7 (1966). The handgun's size made it easy to carry and conceal, which in turn made it susceptible to "clandestine acquisition," S.Rep. No. 90-1097, at 79, and "criminal use," S.Rep. No. 89-1866, at 4.
Overall, the government has marshaled evidence showing that Congress was focused on a particular problem: young persons under 21, who are immature and prone to violence, easily accessing handguns, which facilitate violent crime, primarily by way of FFLs. Accordingly, Congress restricted the ability of young persons under 21 to purchase handguns from FFLs. See 18 U.S.C. § 922(b)(1).
We find that the government has satisfied its burden of showing a reasonable means-ends fit between the challenged federal laws and an important government
Second, Congress selected means that were reasonably adapted to achieving that objective. Congress found that the ease with which young persons under 21 could access handguns — as opposed to other guns — was contributing to violent crime, and also found that FFLs — as opposed to other sources — constituted the central conduit of handgun traffic to young persons under 21. Congress, in turn, reasonably tailored a solution to the particular problem: Congress restricted the ability of persons under 21 to purchase handguns from FFLs, while allowing (i) 18-to-20-year-old persons to purchase long-guns, (ii) persons under 21 to acquire handguns from parents or guardians, and (iii) persons under 21 to possess handguns and long-guns. See 18 U.S.C. § 922(b)(1), (c)(1); see also supra, Section I.B.
Alternatively, Congress could have prohibited all persons under 21 from possessing handguns — or all guns, for that matter. But Congress deliberately adopted a calibrated, compromise approach. See 114 Cong. Rec. at 12309 (Sen. Dodd) ("At the most [the relevant provisions] could cause minor inconveniences to certain youngsters... by requiring that a parent or guardian over 21 years of age make a handgun purchase for any person under 21."); see also S. Rep. 90-1097, at 79 (stating that "a minor or juvenile would not be restricted from owning, or learning the proper usage of [a] firearm, since any firearm which his parent or guardian desired him to have could be obtained for the minor by the parent or guardian"); accord S.Rep. No. 89-1866, at 58.
Since 1968, the means-ends fit between the ban and its objective has retained its reasonableness. The threat posed by 18-to-20-year-olds with easy access to handguns endures. In 1999, for example, one senator noted:
145 Cong. Rec. 7503 (1999) (statement of Sen. Charles Schumer); see also 145 Cong. Rec. 18119 (1999) ("Studies show that one in four gun murders are committed by people aged 18 to 20.") (statement of Rep. Grace Napolitano).
U.S. Dep't of the Treasury & U.S. Dep't of Justice, Gun Crime in the Age Group 18-20, at 2 (June 1999) (citations omitted); see also id. at 3 ("Handguns comprised 85 percent of the crime guns known to be recovered from 18 to 20 year olds" in twenty-seven cities participating in the study).
Recent data confirm that preventing handguns from easily falling into the hands of 18-to-20-year-olds remains critical to public safety. An FBI Uniform Crime Report for 2009 shows that persons aged 19, 18, and 20 accounted for the first, second, and third highest percentages of arrests, respectively, for any age up to age 24 (after which data are reported by age group). U.S. Dep't of Justice & Fed. Bureau of Investigation, Crime in the United States 2009, Table 38: Arrests by Age (Sept.2010), http://www2.fbi.gov/ucr/cius2009/data/table_38.html (last visited Oct. 18, 2012) ("2009 CIUS Report") (reflecting: age 18 (4.8%); age 19 (5.0%); and age 20 (4.6%)). In 2009, 18-to-20-year-olds accounted for over 19% of all murder and non-negligent manslaughter arrests, 14% of all arrests for forcible rape, almost 24% of all robbery arrests, and 12% of all aggravated assault arrests, see id., even though they comprised only about 4.3% of the population.
We therefore hold that the challenged federal laws are constitutional under the Second Amendment. Heller does not cast doubt on them.
We also reject Appellants' contention that the ban violates the equal protection component of the Fifth Amendment. "[E]qual protection analysis requires strict scrutiny of a legislative classification only when the classification impermissibly interferes with the exercise of a fundamental right or operates to the peculiar advantage of a suspect class." Mass. Bd. of Ret. v. Murgia, 427 U.S. 307, 312, 96 S.Ct. 2562, 49 L.Ed.2d 520
Unlike race- or gender-based classifications, which require a "tighter fit between the discriminatory means and the legitimate ends they serve," the government may "discriminate on the basis of age without offending" the constitutional guarantee of equal protection "if the age classification in question is rationally related to a legitimate state interest." Id. at 83-84, 120 S.Ct. 631. "[W]hen conducting rational basis review," a court "will not overturn" the legislation "unless the varying treatment of different groups or persons is so unrelated to the achievement of any combination of legitimate purposes that we can only conclude that the government's actions were irrational." Id. at 84, 120 S.Ct. 631 (internal quotation marks and alterations omitted). "[B]ecause an age classification is presumptively rational, the individual challenging its constitutionality bears the burden of proving the facts on which the classification is apparently based could not reasonably be conceived to be true by the governmental decisionmaker." Id. at 84, 120 S.Ct. 631 (internal quotation marks omitted).
For the same reasons that the challenged laws are reasonably adapted to an important state interest, see supra Section III.E, the laws are rationally related to a legitimate state interest. Appellants have failed to show that Congress irrationally imposed age qualifications on commercial arms sales.
The government also points the court to an ATF Chief Counsel Opinion, which advises — in response to a private inquiry — that an FFL may lawfully sell a firearm to a parent or guardian who is purchasing it for a minor provided that the minor is not otherwise prohibited from receiving or possessing a firearm. Letter from Daniel Hartnett, Asst. Dir., Criminal Enforcement, ATF, to Sig Shore, 23362 (Dec. 5, 1983).
Today — as mentioned supra, Section I.B. — all fifty States (and the District of Columbia) have imposed minimum-age qualifications on the use or purchase of particular firearms. Thirty-five States have Second Amendment analogues in their respective constitutions.
Appellants first argue that 18-to-20-year-olds have a Second Amendment right to purchase firearms from FFLs because, at the time of the founding, 18-to-20-year-olds were assigned to serve in the militia and militia duty necessarily implies the right to purchase firearms. The 1792 Militia Act provided that "each and every free able-bodied white male citizen of the respective States, resident therein, who is or shall be of the age of eighteen years, and under the age of forty-five years (except as is herein after excepted) shall severally and respectively be enrolled in the militia." Militia Act § 1, 1 Stat. 271. But Appellants' militia-based attack on the federal laws at bar is unavailing. First, the right to arms is not co-extensive with the duty to serve in the militia. See Heller, 554 U.S. at 589-94, 128 S.Ct. 2783 (decoupling the former from the latter). Second, if the right to arms and the duty to serve in the militia were linked in the manner that Appellants declare, then Appellants' argument proves too much. In some colonies, able-bodied sixteen-year-olds were obligated to serve in the militia, and yet, Appellants assure us that they are not challenging restrictions on handgun possession by or sales to persons under age 18. E.g., Act of Apr. 3, 1778, ch. 33, 1778 N.Y. Laws 62 (assigning to militia "every able bodied male person [with exceptions] from sixteen years of age to fifty"). Third, in some colonies and States, the minimum age of militia service either dipped below age 18 or crept to age 21, depending on legislative need. Compare An Act for the Better Regulating [of] the Militia, ch. 20, §§ 1, 4, 1777 N.J. Acts 26 (setting minimum age at 16 in 1777), with An Act to embody, for a limited Time, One Thousand of the Militia of this State, for the Defence of the Frontiers thereof, ch. 24, §§ 3-4, 1778 N.J. Acts 58, 58-69 (setting minimum age at 21, but reserving right to accept age 16-21, in 1778). Such fluctuation undermines Appellants' militia-based claim that the right to purchase arms must fully vest precisely at age 18 — not earlier or later. Indeed, the 1792 Militia Act gave States discretion to impose age qualifications on service, and several States chose to enroll only persons age 21 or over, or required parental consent for persons under 21. E.g., An Act to regulate the Militia, § 2, 1843 Ohio Acts 53, 53 (setting minimum age at 21). And this is all not to mention the anachronism at play: we no longer have a founding-era-style militia.
Appellants also argue that a Second Amendment right to purchase firearms from FFLs vests at age 18 because the age of majority is now 18. True, in the 1970s, States lowered the age of majority for most purposes from 21 to 18. But "majority or minority is a status," not a "fixed or vested right." Jeffrey F. Ghent, Statutory Change of Age of Majority as Affecting Pre-existing Status or Rights, 75 A.L.R.3d 228 § 3 (1977). The terms "majority" and "minority" lack content without reference to the right at issue. Seventeen-year-olds may not vote or serve in the military, while 18-year-olds may. Twenty-year-olds may not purchase alcohol (by state statute), purchase lottery tickets in some States (e.g., Ariz.Rev.Stat. § 5-515(a)), purchase handguns in some States (by state statute), or purchase handguns from FFLs (by federal statute) — while 21-year-olds may. Neither the Twenty-Sixth Amendment nor state law setting the age of majority at 18 compels Congress or the States to select 18 as the minimum age to purchase alcohol, lottery tickets, or handguns.
The 2009 CIUS Report was not an aberration. Similar to the 2009 report, the 2010 CIUS Report shows that 18-, 19-, and 20-year-olds accounted for the three highest percentages of arrests for any age up to 24 (after which data are reported by age group); and, like the 2009 report, the 2010 report shows that 18-to-20-year-olds accounted for a disproportionately high percentage of arrests for violent crimes. See U.S. Dep't of Justice & Fed. Bureau of Investigation, Crime in the United States 2010, Table 38: Arrests by Age (Sept.2011), http://www.fbi.gov/about-us/cjis/ucr/crime-in-the-u.s/2010/crime-in-the-u.s.-2010/tables/10tbl39.xls (last visited Oct. 10, 2012) (reflecting: age 18 (4.6%); age 19 (4.9%); age 20 (4.7%)).
Furthermore, even putting aside deference, modern scientific research supports the commonsense notion that 18-to-20-year-olds tend to be more impulsive than young adults aged 21 and over. See, e.g., Brief for the Am. Med. Ass'n et al. as Amici Curiae in Support of Neither Party, Miller v. Alabama, ___ U.S. ___, 132 S.Ct. 2455, 183 L.Ed.2d 407 (2012) (Nos. 10-9646, 10-9647), 2012 WL 121237, at 19-20 ("The brain's frontal lobes are still structurally immature well into late adolescence, and the prefrontal cortex is `one of the last brain regions to mature.' This, in turn, means that `response inhibition, emotional regulation, planning and organization ... continue to develop between adolescence and young adulthood.'" (citations omitted)); Lawrence Steinberg et al., Age Differences in Future Orientation and Delay Discounting, 80 Child Dev. 28, 40-41 (2009) ("[C]hanges in impulse control and planning are mediated by a `cognitive control' network ... which matures more gradually and over a longer period of time, into early adulthood.").