PAEZ, Circuit Judge:
A state sets itself on a collision course with the First Amendment when it chooses to popularly elect its judges but restricts a candidate's campaign speech. The conflict arises from the fundamental tension between the ideal of apolitical judicial independence and the critical nature of unfettered speech in the electoral political process. Here we must decide whether several provisions in the Arizona Code of Judicial Conduct restricting judicial candidate speech run afoul of First Amendment protections. Because we are concerned with content-based restrictions on electioneering-related speech, those protections are at their apex. Arizona, like every other state, has a compelling interest in the reality and appearance of an impartial judiciary, but speech restrictions must be narrowly tailored to serve that interest. We hold that several provisions of the Arizona Code of Judicial Conduct unconstitutionally restrict the speech of non judge candidates because the restrictions are not sufficiently narrowly tailored to survive strict scrutiny. Accordingly, we reverse the district court's grant of summary judgment in favor of Defendants.
Arizona counties with fewer than 250,000 people popularly elect local judicial officers. See Ariz. Const. art. VI, §§ 12, 40.
Plaintiff Randolph Wolfson was an unsuccessful candidate for judicial office in Mohave County, Arizona in 2006 and 2008. Wolfson I, 616 F.3d at 1052-53. He intends to run in a future election. Id. at 1054-55. As a candidate, Wolfson wished to conduct a number of activities he believed to be prohibited by the Code, but refrained from doing so, fearing professional discipline.
Wolfson challenges five clauses of Rule 4.1 of the Code (the "Rules"):
Ariz.Rev.Stat. Ann. § 17A, Sup.Ct. Rules, Rule 81, Code of Jud. Conduct (2009).
This is the second time that this case is before us. We previously held in Wolfson I that Wolfson's challenges to these clauses (hereinafter the "solicitation" clause (6) and "political activities" clauses, (2)-(5)) were justiciable and remanded them to the district court to consider them on the merits. Wolfson I, 616 F.3d at 1054-62, 1066-67. With respect to his challenge to a now-defunct "pledges and promises" clause, we held that Wolfson lacked standing to challenge it insofar as it applied to the speech of judges. Id. at 1064. "Wolfson cannot assert the constitutional rights of judges when he is not, and may never be, a member of that group." Id.
On remand, ruling on cross-motions for summary judgment, the district court applied a balancing test articulated by the Seventh Circuit in Siefert v. Alexander, 608 F.3d 974 (7th Cir.2010), and Bauer v. Shepard, 620 F.3d 704 (7th Cir.2010), and upheld the constitutionality of the five challenged Code provisions. Wolfson II, 822 F.Supp.2d at 929-30. The balancing test from Siefert/Bauer "derives from the line of Supreme Court cases upholding the limited power of governments to restrict their employees' political speech in order to promote the efficiency and integrity of government services." Id. at 929. The district court held that this standard "strikes an appropriate balance between the weaker First Amendment rights at stake and the stronger State interests in regulating the way it chooses its judges," apparently because the speech at issue was not "core speech" deserving of strict scrutiny but "behavior short of true speech." Id. at 929-30.
The district court proceeded to balance the interests of the state against the interests of a judicial candidate. With respect to the political activities restrictions (the campaigning and endorsement clauses), the district court held that "[e]ndorsements, making speeches, and soliciting funds on behalf of other candidates is not... core political speech." Id. at 931. The district court distinguished between announcing one's own political views or qualifications — speech protected by Republican Party of Minn. v. White, 536 U.S. 765, 788, 122 S.Ct. 2528, 153 L.Ed.2d
Id. at 932. The district court assumed the constitutional validity of the Rules restricting political activities as applied to sitting judges, holding that "the Pickering line of cases [upholding the government's power to restrict employees' political speech to promote efficiency and integrity of government services] remains relevant to restrictions on the speech of sitting judges." Id. The court concluded that Rules 4.1(A)(2)-(5) appropriately balanced the state's interest in "protecting the due process rights of litigants and ensuring the real and perceived impartiality of the judiciary" against a candidate's interest in "participating in the political campaigns of other candidates" and upheld the political activities clauses as constitutional. Id.
As for the solicitation clause (Rule 4.1(A)(6)) prohibiting a judicial candidate from "personally solicit[ing] or accept[ing] campaign contributions other than through a campaign committee," the district court held that it was constitutional as applied to non judge candidates because it struck "a constitutional balance" between the state's interest in the appearance and actuality of an impartial judiciary and a candidate's need for funds. Id. at 931. The district court found that all forms of personal solicitation, whether in-person or via signed mass mailings, created "the same risk of coercion and bias." Id. Wolfson timely appealed.
We review de novo an order granting summary judgment on the constitutionality of a statute. See Nunez by Nunez v. City of San Diego, 114 F.3d 935, 940 (9th Cir.1997).
Wolfson seeks to invalidate the challenged Rules on their face, including as to sitting judges campaigning for retention or reelection. In Wolfson I, however, we held that "Wolfson cannot assert the constitutional rights of judges when he is not, and may never be, a member of that group." 616 F.3d at 1064. Nonetheless, although we reject the Arizona defendants' argument, which the district court adopted, that the balancing test applicable to government employee speech cases also applies to sitting judges and thus fairly extends to non judge candidates campaigning for office, we must establish the scope of our review of the challenged Rules.
We decline to adopt the district court's approach because such reasoning requires a series of unnecessary constitutional decisions.
We are not persuaded that "fundamental fairness," see Wolfson II, 822 F.Supp.2d at 929, warrants making an advisory decision about the constitutional speech rights of judges who are not presently before us and whose rights Wolfson cannot assert, Wolfson I, 616 F.3d at 1064. Under strict scrutiny, see Part III.A, the proponents of a speech regulation must establish a compelling state interest served by the regulation. Neither the Commission nor the State Bar Counsel has argued that Arizona has a compelling state interest in applying the same election regulations to incumbent sitting judges as to candidates who are not sitting judges — only that such an equal application is principled, logical, and fair.
Our decision to limit our review to non judge candidates is ultimately based on judicial restraint. We need not decide today what restrictions on judges' speech are constitutionally justified by the interest in allowing the judiciary to function optimally, nor are we squarely presented with that question. We neither "`anticipate a question of constitutional law in advance of the necessity of deciding it' nor `formulate a rule of constitutional law broader than is required by the precise facts to which it is to be applied.'" Wash. State Grange v. Wash. State Republican Party, 552 U.S. 442, 450, 128 S.Ct. 1184, 170 L.Ed.2d 151 (2008) (quoting Ashwander v. TVA, 297 U.S. 288, 347, 56 S.Ct. 466, 80 L.Ed. 688 (1936) (Brandeis, J., concurring)). The only constitutional question we address is whether the challenged Rules violate the First Amendment rights of non judge candidates.
Strict scrutiny applies to this First Amendment challenge. The regulations in question are content- and speaker-based
Content-based restrictions on speech receive strict scrutiny. See United States v. Playboy Entm't Grp., Inc., 529 U.S. 803, 813, 120 S.Ct. 1878, 146 L.Ed.2d 865 (2000). Here, the Rules at issue
Carey v. Wolnitzek, 614 F.3d 189, 198-99 (6th Cir.2010). The canons do not address any of the "categorical carve-outs" of proscribable speech. See id. at 199. Nor are they the types of regulations to which the Supreme Court has applied a less rigorous standard of review, such as time, place and manner restrictions, commercial speech, or expressive conduct. Id.
Every sister circuit except the Seventh that has considered similar regulations since White I has applied strict scrutiny as the standard of review. See Wersal v. Sexton, 674 F.3d 1010, 1019 (8th Cir.2012) (en banc), cert. denied, ___ U.S. ___, 133 S.Ct. 209, 184 L.Ed.2d 40 (2012); Carey, 614 F.3d at 198-99; White II, 416 F.3d at 749, 764-65; Weaver v. Bonner, 309 F.3d 1312, 1319 (11th Cir.2002). We are not persuaded by the Seventh Circuit's approach, which the Arizona defendants urge us to adopt by asking us to affirm the district court.
The Seventh Circuit treated the solicitation ban in Siefert as a "campaign finance regulation" and applied the "closely drawn scrutiny" framework of Buckley v. Valeo, 608 F.3d at 988 (citing 424 U.S. 1, 96 S.Ct. 612, 46 L.Ed.2d 659 (1976) (per curiam)). The court treated the solicitation ban like a restriction on a campaign contribution — though by default, because the solicitation ban was not an expenditure restriction. Id. Contrary to the Arizona defendants' argument, the solicitation clause at issue here is not a restriction on a campaign contribution within the meaning of Buckley, 424 U.S. at 26-27, 96 S.Ct. 612. Arizona's solicitation ban does nothing at all to limit contributions to a judicial candidate's campaign — either in amount or from certain persons or groups. Contribution restrictions, like those at issue in Buckley, restrict the speech of potential contributors. 424 U.S. at 21-22, 96 S.Ct. 612. The Rule at issue here restricts only the solicitation for the contributions — the speech of the candidate.
Considering a rule prohibiting a judge or judicial candidate from making endorsements or speaking on behalf of a partisan candidate or platform, the Seventh Circuit applied "a balancing approach" derived from a line of cases determining the speech rights of government employees. Siefert, 608 F.3d at 983-87. As noted in Part II.B, here we consider only the speech rights of Wolfson as a private citizen and judicial candidate — not yet, and perhaps never, a government employee. "[Wolfson] [i]s not a sitting judge but a challenger; he ha[s] not voluntarily entered into an employment relationship with the State or surrendered any First Amendment rights. His speech may not be controlled or abridged in this manner." See White I, 536 U.S at 796, 122 S.Ct. 2528 (Kennedy, J., concurring). For the reasons discussed above, we decline to extend the rationale from the employee-speech cases to apply a lower level of scrutiny to the restrictions on Wolfson's First Amendment rights during a judicial campaign.
The Seventh Circuit also reasoned that a balancing approach was appropriate because endorsements are "a different form of speech" outside of "core" political speech thus having "limited communicative value," and when judges make endorsements they are "speaking as judges, and trading on the prestige of their office to advance other political ends." Siefert, 608 F.3d at 983, 984, 986.
We share the Seventh Circuit's concerns about protecting litigants' due process rights, which we recognize as a compelling state interest. That court reasoned that because "restrictions on judicial speech may, in some circumstances, be required by the Due Process Clause," states could regulate even political speech by judges if the regulations served the
Weaver, 309 F.3d at 1320; accord White I, 536 U.S. at 792, 122 S.Ct. 2528 (O'Connor, J., concurring) ("If the State has a problem with judicial impartiality, it is largely one the State brought upon itself by continuing the practice of popularly electing judges.").
Under strict scrutiny, the Arizona defendants have the burden to prove that the challenged Rules further a compelling interest and are narrowly tailored to achieve that interest. Citizens United, 558 U.S. at 340, 130 S.Ct. 876. First we consider Arizona's state interests. Then, we analyze whether the solicitation clause (Rule 4.1(A)(6)) and the political activities clauses (Rules 4.1(A)(2)-(5)) are narrowly tailored to serve those interests.
Every court to consider the issue has affirmed that states have a compelling interest in the appearance and actuality of an impartial judiciary. See, e.g., White I, 536 U.S. at 775-76, 122 S.Ct. 2528. The meaning of "impartiality" is lack of bias for or against either party to a case. Id. at 775, 122 S.Ct. 2528. This definition accords with the idea that due process violations arise only in case-specific contexts. The Supreme Court has also recognized that states have a compelling interest in preventing corruption or the appearance of corruption through campaign finance regulations. Buckley, 424 U.S. at 26-27, 96 S.Ct. 612; see also Citizens United, 558 U.S. at 357, 130 S.Ct. 876. Thus, we recognize that Arizona has a compelling interest in an uncorrupt judiciary that appears to be and is impartial to the parties who appear before its judges.
The Arizona defendants also argue for two other compelling interests that we do not find persuasive. First, the Commission defendants argue that "the State has a compelling interest in preventing candidates (who will after all be the next judges if and when elected) from trampling on the interests of impartiality and public confidence." This argument is, essentially, that states have a compelling interest in regulating candidates' speech; we do not find an interest in regulating speech per se to be compelling. We do agree, however, that states have a compelling interest in maintaining public confidence in the judiciary. In a similar vein, State Bar Counsel argues that Arizona has a compelling interest in avoiding "judicial campaign abuses that threaten to imperil public confidence in the fairness and integrity of the nation's elected judges." But, as explained above, any imperilment of public confidence has its roots in the very nature of judicial elections, and not in the speech of candidates who must participate in those elections to become judges. See White I, 536 U.S. at 792, 122 S.Ct. 2528 (O'Connor, J., concurring).
Second, the Commission defendants argue that Arizona has a compelling interest in "preventing judges and judicial candidates from using the prestige of their office or potential office for purposes not related to their judicial duties." We are not persuaded by this argument as applied to non judge candidates, who cannot abuse the prestige of an office they do not yet and may never hold.
The solicitation clause prohibits a judicial candidate from "personally solicit[ing] or accept[ing] campaign contributions other than through a campaign committee authorized by Rule 4.4." Rule 4.1(A)(6).
Arizona's sweeping definition of "personally solicit" encompasses methods not likely to impinge on even the appearance of impartiality. The Sixth Circuit recently invalidated a similar clause in Kentucky that also extended beyond one-on-one, in-person solicitations to group solicitations, telephone calls, and letters. Carey, 614 F.3d at 204. We agree with our sister court's cogent analysis of this issue. "[I]ndirect methods of solicitation [such as speeches to large groups and signed mass mailings] present little or no risk of undue pressure or the appearance of a quid pro quo." Id. at 205. The clauses are also underinclusive: a personal solicitation by a campaign committee member who may be the candidate's best friend or close professional associate (such as a law practice partner) is likely to have a greater risk for "coercion and undue appearance" than a signed mass mailing or request during a speech to a large group. Id. Moreover, the Code does not prohibit a candidate's campaign committee from disclosing to the candidate the names of contributors and solicited non-contributors.
Id.
We analyze Rules 4.1(A)(2)-(5) as the "political activities" clauses. Judicial candidates are prohibited from speechifying for another candidate or organization, endorsing or opposing another candidate, fundraising for another candidate or organization, or actively taking part in any political campaign other than his or her own. These clauses are also not sufficiently narrowly tailored to serve the state's interest in an impartial judiciary, and are thus unconstitutional restrictions on political speech of non judge candidates for judicial office.
Rules 4.1(A)(2)-(4) — prohibiting speechifying, endorsements, and fundraising — present the closest question. There is an argument that these rules are sufficiently narrowly tailored to be constitutional because they curtail speech that evidences bias towards a particular (potential) party within the scope of White I: the candidate or political organization endorsed or spoken of favorably by the judicial candidate. A plurality of the Eighth Circuit, sitting en banc, upheld a nearly identical Minnesota prohibition on a judge or judicial candidate endorsing "another candidate for public office" because such an endorsement "creates a risk of partiality towards the endorsed party and his or her supporters." Wersal, 674 F.3d at 1024, 1025. The plurality concluded that the clause was narrowly tailored to serve the state's compelling interest in the appearance and reality of an impartial judiciary. Id. at 1028.
White I, 536 U.S. at 779-80, 122 S.Ct. 2528. Here too, Rules 4.1(A)(2)-(4) are "woefully underinclusive" because they only address speech made after a candidate has filed his intention to enter the race. Id. at 780, 122 S.Ct. 2528. Contrary to the dissent, we fail to see why this same concern does not apply here.
Moreover, the Arizona defendants have failed to show why the less restrictive remedy of recusal of a successful candidate from any case in which he or she was involved in a party's political campaign or gave an endorsement is an unworkable alternative. "[B]ecause restricting speech should be the government's tool of last resort, the availability of obvious less-restrictive alternatives renders a speech restriction overinclusive." Valle Del Sol Inc. v. Whiting, 709 F.3d 808, 826 (9th Cir.2013). Here, it seems that if a candidate indeed becomes a judge, a less restrictive means of addressing the state's concerns would be to require recusal in cases where the new judge's bias against or in favor of a party is clear.
We hold Rule 4.1(A)(5), which prohibits a judicial candidate from "actively tak[ing] part in any political campaign other than his or her own campaign for election, reelection, or retention in office" to be unconstitutional because it is overbroad. By its terms, it is not limited to restrictions on participation in political campaigns on behalf of persons who may become parties to a suit, but may also include political campaigns on ballot propositions and other issues, including political campaigns for ballot propositions that present no risk of impartiality towards future parties. Thus, Rule 4.1(A)(5) unconstitutionally prohibits protected speech about legal issues. White I, 536 U.S. at 776-78, 122 S.Ct. 2528.
For these reasons, we reverse the district court's grant of summary judgment to the Arizona defendants. We hold that strict scrutiny applies and that the challenged portions of the Arizona Code of Judicial conduct unconstitutionally restrict the speech of non judge judicial candidates. We remand the case for further proceedings consistent with this opinion.
BERZON, Circuit Judge, concurring:
Sitting for judicial election while judging cases, Justice Otto Kaus famously quipped, is like "brushing your teeth in the bathroom and trying not to notice the crocodile in the bathtub." Joseph R. Grodin, In Pursuit of Justice: Reflections of a State Supreme Court Justice 177 (1989) (quoting Kaus). Kaus would know. He sat on the California Supreme Court from 1981 to 1985, Gerald T. McLaughlin, Memorial Dedication to Otto Kaus, 30 Loy. L.A. L.Rev. 923, 923 (1997), having narrowly won a retention election in 1982 and retiring from the court soon before the 1986 vote that would unseat three of his former colleagues, Stephen R. Barnett, Otto and the Court, 30 Loy. L.A. L.Rev. 943, 947 & n.19 (1997).
Kaus' point about the psychology of judging applies outside the context of judicial elections, for the temptation to engage in overt political behavior affects judges generally. And so I write separately to identify, and hopefully to tame, the "crocodile" stalking today's majority opinion: the prospect that the principles we apply now will be used in future litigation to challenge the constitutionality of restrictions on the political behavior of sitting judges. The opinion studiously — and designedly — does not address that issue. But it is worth explaining why, in my view, the considerations pertinent to evaluating the complex of constitutional issues raised by
Today's opinion addresses the constitutionality of certain provisions of the Arizona Code of Judicial Conduct ("Code") only as they apply to judicial candidates who, like Wolfson, have not yet ascended to the bench. It does not decide those provisions' constitutionality as they apply to elected judges who, like Kaus, have already taken their oaths of office. Still less does it decide the constitutionality of restrictions on the political activity of judges who, like us on the federal bench, "hold their Offices during good Behaviour," U.S. Const. art. III, § 1, and never sit for election. In the name of prudence and constitutional avoidance, the majority's opinion rightly reserves judgment on the constitutionality of restricting the speech of sitting judges, an issue neither properly before us nor necessary to the resolution of this case.
I emphasize the limited scope of today's decision for fear that future litigants might otherwise seek to obscure it, despite the repeated admonishments in the opinion. Of the five Code provisions we strike today, only one — the solicitation ban — directly relates to a judicial candidate's own campaign for office.
In my view, that is not so, for at least two reasons: The analytic framework applicable to political restrictions on sitting judges may well differ from the one we apply today. And the compelling state interest that could well justify such restrictions differs from the one emphasized in the majority opinion. I address each difference in turn.
In applying strict scrutiny to a judicial candidate who is not now a judge, today's majority opinion rightly rejects the Seventh Circuit's approach, which applies to political restrictions on elected sitting judges a balancing test derived from the
The Constitution permits the government to prohibit its employees from speaking about matters of public concern where the government's interest "in promoting the efficiency of the public services it performs through its employees" outweighs the First Amendment interest in speech. Pickering v. Bd. of Educ. of Twp. High Sch. Dist. 205, Will Cnty., Ill., 391 U.S. 563, 568, 88 S.Ct. 1731, 20 L.Ed.2d 811 (1968). The Pickering balancing test seeks "both to promote the individual and societal interests that are served when employees speak as citizens on matters of public concern and to respect the needs of government employers attempting to perform their important public functions." Garcetti v. Ceballos, 547 U.S. 410, 420, 126 S.Ct. 1951, 164 L.Ed.2d 689 (2006). And that test recognizes that "there are certain governmental functions that cannot operate without some restrictions on particular kinds of speech." Citizens United v. Fed. Election Comm'n, 558 U.S. 310, 341, 130 S.Ct. 876, 175 L.Ed.2d 753 (2010).
Republican Party of Minnesota v. White, 536 U.S. 765, 122 S.Ct. 2528, 153 L.Ed.2d 694 (2002), did not decide whether the public employee speech cases would justify restrictions on judges' active support for political causes or the candidacies of others. Justice Kennedy, who was a member of the five justice majority, wrote a separate concurrence, explaining this limitation: "Whether the rationale of Pickering [, 391 U.S. 563, 88 S.Ct. 1731], and Connick v. Myers, 461 U.S. 138, 103 S.Ct. 1684, 75 L.Ed.2d 708 (1983), could be extended to allow a general speech restriction on sitting judges — regardless of whether they are campaigning — in order to promote the efficient administration of justice, is not an issue raised here." White, 536 U.S. at 796, 122 S.Ct. 2528 (Kennedy, J., concurring).
In Siefert, 608 F.3d at 985, the Seventh Circuit extended the public employee speech cases to a provision of the Wisconsin Code of Judicial Conduct prohibiting an elected sitting judge from "[p]ublicly endors[ing] or speak[ing] on behalf of [a political party's] candidates or platforms," id. at 978-79. It reasoned that the government's authority as an employer, "its duty to promote the efficiency of the public services it performs," and the imperative that "the work of the judiciary conform[] with the due process requirements of the Constitution" justified a less rigorous balancing test for restrictions on elected sitting judges' participation in the political campaigns or candidacies of others. Id. at 985. In a subsequent decision, the Seventh Circuit extended this balancing test to provisions of the Indiana Code of Judicial Conduct prohibiting elected judges from leading or holding office in political organizations or making speeches on behalf of such organizations. Bauer, 620 F.3d at 710-11.
The core rationale of the public employee speech cases, on which Siefert and Bauer relied, does not apply to the case presently before us. Wolfson has never been an employee of Arizona, let alone a judge. Indeed, he may never become one. While the public employee speech cases do not rest solely on the now-antiquated principle that the government can condition employment on the waiver of First Amendment rights, see Myers, 461 U.S. at 143-44, 103 S.Ct. 1684, the nature of government employment is a necessary
But our refusal to apply to a judicial candidate not yet a state employee a balancing test derived from the public employee speech cases says nothing whatever about the applicability of such a test to individuals who have already taken their oaths of judicial office and already receive wages from the state. That question remains unanswered. Resolving the First Amendment challenge of a sitting judge to similar restrictions on his speech will require answering it. And, without prejudging whether we should adopt the Siefert analysis for restrictions on political activity by sitting judges on behalf of political causes or the candidacies of others, I suggest that the analogy to the Pickering line of cases has much to commend it.
Even if we determined that restrictions on the political activity of sitting judges were subject to strict scrutiny, the state interest supporting such a restriction would be far stronger than the one we hold inadequate to justify the restrictions on judicial candidate Wolfson's speech today.
The Supreme Court has recognized as a "vital state interest" the interest in maintaining those "safeguard[s] against judicial campaign abuses that threaten to imperil public confidence in the fairness and integrity of the nation's elected judges." Caperton v. A.T. Massey Coal Co., 556 U.S. 868, 889, 129 S.Ct. 2252, 173 L.Ed.2d 1208 (2009) (emphasis added) (internal quotation marks and citation omitted). Preserving public confidence includes maintaining the perception of judicial propriety. In other words, "`justice must satisfy the appearance of justice.'" In re Murchison, 349 U.S. 133, 136, 75 S.Ct. 623, 99 L.Ed. 942 (1955) (quoting Offutt v. United States, 348 U.S. 11, 14, 75 S.Ct. 11, 99 L.Ed. 11 (1954)). "[T]he appearance of evenhanded justice ... is at the core of due process." Mayberry v. Pennsylvania, 400 U.S. 455, 469, 91 S.Ct. 499, 27 L.Ed.2d 532 (1971) (Harlan, J., concurring).
The majority opinion, taking its cue from Supreme Court cases on judicial elections, focuses its strict scrutiny analysis on the interest in preserving the actuality and appearance of judicial impartiality. The case law's emphasis on impartiality derives from the obligations imposed by the due process clause, particularly "the proposition that an impartial judge is essential to due process." White, 536 U.S. at 776, 122 S.Ct. 2528. This compelling interest in preserving the appearance of impartiality is both weighty and narrow: weighty, because it rises to the level of a constitutional obligation, requiring a judge to recuse himself from a particular case in the name
But I would define the state's interest in preserving public confidence in its judiciary more broadly, as reaching beyond the process due specific litigants in particular cases. Maintaining public trust in the judiciary as an institution driven by legal principles rather than political concerns is a structural imperative. The rule of law depends upon it.
The fundamental importance of this structural imperative has been recognized from the founding of the nation. As Alexander Hamilton emphasized in The Federalist No. 78, the courts possess "neither FORCE nor WILL, but merely judgment...." Id. at 433 (Clinton Rossiter ed., 1961). Deprived of those alternative sources of power, the authority of the judiciary instead "lies ... in its legitimacy, a product of substance and perception that shows itself in the people's acceptance of the Judiciary as fit to determine what the... law means and to declare what it demands." Planned Parenthood of Se. Pa. v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833, 865, 112 S.Ct. 2791, 120 L.Ed.2d 674 (1992); see also White, 536 U.S. at 793, 122 S.Ct. 2528 (Kennedy, J., concurring) ("The power and the prerogative of a court ... rest, in the end, upon the respect accorded to its judgments."). It is the courts' perceived legitimacy as institutions grounded in established legal principles, not partisanship, "that leads decisions to be obeyed and averts vigilantism and civil strife." Bauer, 620 F.3d at 712. Loss of judicial legitimacy thus corrodes the rule of law, "sap[ping] the foundations of public and private confidence, and ... introduc[ing] in its stead universal distrust and distress." The Federalist No. 78, at 438. In this sense, "[t]he rule of law, which is a foundation of freedom, presupposes a functioning judiciary respected for its independence, its professional attainments, and the absolute probity of its judges." NY State Bd. of Elections v. Lopez Torres, 552 U.S. 196, 212, 128 S.Ct. 791, 169 L.Ed.2d 665 (2008) (Kennedy, J., concurring).
This nation's political history demonstrates the disastrous effects of the perceived politicization of the courts. Charges that King George "ha[d] obstructed the Administration of Justice" and "ha[d] made judges dependent on his Will alone ...." were among the founding generation's justifications for the 1776 revolution. The Declaration of Independence para. 11 (U.S.1776). Similar concerns apply outside the context of a monarchy: Where the judiciary is drawn into the political intrigues of its coordinate branches, the public might well "fear that the pestilential breath of faction may poison the fountains of justice. The habit of being continually marshaled on opposite sides will be too apt to stifle the voice both of law and of equity." The Federalist No. 81, at 452 (Alexander Hamilton) (Clinton Rossiter ed., 1961).
The defendants here express precisely this concern — that if sitting judges may support the campaigns of others, the public will perceive them as masters of the political game, powerbrokers "trading on the prestige of their office to advance other political ends...." Siefert, 608 F.3d at 984; see also Model Code of Judicial Conduct R. 4.1, cmt.4 (2011) (justifying prohibitions on endorsements and speeches on behalf of other candidates as "prevent[ing sitting judges] from abusing the prestige of judicial office to advance the interests of others"). The opposite fear is equally justified: Today's powerbroker is tomorrow's pawn, as the political winds shift and the next election cycle approaches. The endorsing judge entwines his fate with whomever he endorses and earns the enmity of his favored politician's opponents. "This kind of personal affiliation between a member of the judiciary and a member of the political branches raises the specter — readily perceived by the general public — that the judge's future rulings will be influenced by this political dependency." Wersal v. Sexton, 674 F.3d 1010, 1034 (8th Cir.2012) (Loken, J., concurring in the judgment) (emphasis in original).
In his concurrence in Wersal, Judge Loken concluded that there is a "compelling state interest ... in protecting the political independence of its judiciary." Id. at 1033. I have no reason at this juncture to come to rest on that question. Instead, I emphasize that, at the very least, there is a powerful state interest in preventing sitting judges from playing the part of political powerbroker and creating the publicly visible interdependence that corrodes confidence in judicial autonomy. Assessing whether that interest qualifies as "compelling," in the lexicon of First Amendment doctrine, awaits a properly presented case — particularly as the issue will never arise if we first determine that the Pickering balancing test, rather than strict scrutiny, applies to speech restrictions on sitting judges.
Almost certainly, a state does not forfeit this powerful interest in judicial autonomy by selecting its judges via popular election. It was in the context of a state prohibition against judicial candidates expressing their personal views on disputed legal and political issues during their own campaigns that the Supreme Court has explained that "`the greater power to dispense with elections altogether does not include the lesser power to conduct elections under conditions of state-imposed voter ignorance. If the State chooses to tap the energy and the legitimizing power of the democratic process, it must accord the participants in that process ... the First Amendment rights that attach to their roles.'" White, 536 U.S. at 788, 122 S.Ct. 2528 (alteration in original) (quoting Renne v. Geary, 501 U.S. 312, 349, 111 S.Ct. 2331, 115 L.Ed.2d
Nor should we forget that our own federal scheme supplements its structural protections for judicial autonomy with direct prohibitions on politicking. Structurally, our Constitution endows judges with life tenure and prohibits the diminution of their salaries. U.S. Const. art. III, § 1. Such protections seek to encourage "that independent spirit in the judges which must be essential to the faithful performance of so arduous a duty," The Federalist No. 78, at 437, and help "preserve[] the independence of the Federal Judiciary," White, 536 U.S. at 795, 122 S.Ct. 2528 (Kennedy, J., concurring). In addition to those structural safeguards the federal judiciary has adopted a code of ethics that regulates directly the behavior of federal judges, including restrictions on supporting the political causes and candidacies of others.
Critically, the state interest in preserving an autonomous judiciary is powerful only insofar as it applies to sitting judges; it has no application to judicial candidates who, like Wolfson, have not yet reached the bench. The spectacle of sitting judges aiding partisan allies in their political struggles corrodes the public repute of the judiciary in a way that the participation of a mere candidate never can. Indeed, the interest in an independent judiciary does not come into existence until a judge assumes office; the politicking of lay people cannot damage the reputation of a body whose ranks they have not yet joined. Individuals who run for judicial office may themselves be officers of political parties or holders of nonjudicial political office when they decide to run for a judgeship. That politicians can become judges is no secret. But that is different from allowing judges to remain or become politicians while still on the bench. Moreover, as the majority opinion explains, a layman who has not yet assumed office has no prestige derived from the office he has not yet attained to lend his political brethren. Essentially, ascending to the bench is like taking the veil, and that veil does not descend until the oath of office is sworn.
Meanwhile, to the extent White sought to preserve voters' access to "relevant information" and to prevent "state-imposed voter ignorance" about the candidates sitting for election, 536 U.S. at 782, 788, 122 S.Ct. 2528 (internal quotation marks omitted), such concerns are weaker for already seated judges. Such judges already possess a record of decisions that interested voters can analyze to inform themselves about the desirability of competing judicial candidates; under White, they are free to campaign for their own reelection by drawing attention to their records on the bench. By contrast, lay people, like Wolfson, who have not yet sat on the bench lack any such judicial record, making their campaign speech — including endorsements — relatively more valuable for what it reveals about how they might perform in office.
In sum, the principles applicable to the constitutionality of political restrictions on sitting judges diverge dramatically from those we apply to today's challenge to restrictions on a judicial candidate not now a judge. The standard of review may well differ. And the powerful interests supporting such restrictions differ, too. I need not address, as the issue is not before us, whether the particular restrictions we review today would be constitutional as applied to sitting judges. But I am quite sure that the analysis required to resolve that question will receive scant support from our decision in this case.
TALLMAN, Circuit Judge, dissenting in part:
I agree with the majority that strict scrutiny — not Seifert — is the appropriate standard. I agree that we should limit our decision to non-incumbent judicial candidates. And I agree that Rules 4.1(a)(5) (campaigning for others) and 4.1(a)(6) (personal solicitation) are unconstitutional as applied to those candidates. I concur in the majority opinion only on those points. I part company with my colleagues as to Rules 4.1(a)(2) (giving speeches on behalf of others), (3) (endorsing others), and (4) (soliciting money for others). These three rules are constitutional because they are narrowly tailored to serve the state's compelling interest in maintaining judicial impartiality and its appearance — the hallmark of government's third branch.
My colleagues acknowledge that these three rules "present the closest question," and that the Eighth Circuit upheld similar ones. Wersal, 674 F.3d at 1024-25.
The majority's timing argument is clever but impractical. Its breadth alone suggests this. The argument would cut down any restriction (a) that is subject to strict scrutiny and (b) that starts to apply to people only after some triggering event. If the restriction's enactment counts as a triggering event, and I don't see why it wouldn't, then strict scrutiny would always be fatal. That cannot be the law.
Moreover, the argument doesn't actually answer the question, which is whether there are less restrictive ways to preserve judicial impartiality and its appearance. Having no rules is, of course, less restrictive. But it isn't an alternative means of furthering the interest at stake here. Any actual alternative will suffer from the timing problem the majority identifies. So the timing argument tells us nothing about which alternative is the least restrictive; it only identifies a problem that all conceivable alternatives share.
The majority's recusal argument, like the timing argument, is too impractical in my view. In Arizona, only very small counties elect judges. And some small counties may well have only one superior court judge. If that one judge campaigns for someone who is then elected sheriff or district attorney, an outside judge would be necessary in every criminal case and in all civil cases involving the county where the district attorney is its lawyer. Constant recusal is no solution.
That's what the Eighth Circuit held in Wersal, after it considered this obvious problem. 674 F.3d at 1027-28. The majority, on the other hand, recognizes the problem, but then sidesteps it, claiming that the state failed to raise it and that dealing with it would require us to speculate. I disagree. There's no need to speculate about something so self-evident. And it's hard to fault the state for failing to dwell on the obvious.
In sum, I don't buy the timing or recusal arguments. And without them, there's nothing that prevents us from declaring that these three rules are the least restrictive means at Arizona's disposal for furthering their compelling interest in maintaining judicial impartiality and its appearance. Simply affixing the label of strict scrutiny and then declaring that unspecified less restrictive means are required gives no guidance as to what rules pass constitutional muster. And it encourages an elective free-for-all that undermines respect for the third branch of government. Because my colleagues disagree, I respectfully dissent.
Ariz.Rev.Stat. Ann. § 17A, Sup.Ct. Rules, Rule 81, Code of Jud. Conduct (2009), Rule 4.1(A)(6).
Ariz.Rev.Stat. Ann. § 17A, Sup.Ct. Rules, Rule 81, Code of Jud. Conduct (2009), Rule 4.1(A)(2)-(5).
Administrative Office of U.S. Courts, Code of Judicial Conduct for United States Judges, Canon 5 (2011).