Per Curiam.
Plaintiffs ask us to declare a constitutional right to "aid-in-dying," which they define (and we refer to herein) as the right of a mentally competent and terminally ill person to obtain a prescription for a lethal dosage of drugs from a physician, to be taken at some point to cause death. Although New York has long recognized a competent adult's right to forgo life-saving medical care, we reject plaintiffs' argument that an individual has a fundamental constitutional right to aid-in-dying as they define it. We also reject plaintiffs' assertion that the State's prohibition on assisted suicide is not rationally related to legitimate state interests.
Plaintiffs filed the instant action against New York State's Attorney General and several district attorneys,
When the complaint was filed, plaintiffs included three mentally competent patients, two of whom were terminally ill, and one of whom was being treated for cancer. The terminally ill plaintiffs have died, and the patient undergoing treatment is in remission. Plaintiffs also include individual medical providers who assert that fear of prosecution has prevented them from exercising their best professional judgment when counseling and treating their patients. They are joined by organizational plaintiff End of Life Choices, which sued on its own behalf and on behalf of its clients, for whom it provides
The Attorney General moved to dismiss the complaint on the grounds that plaintiffs failed to state a cause of action and did not present a justiciable controversy (see CPLR 3211 [a] [7], [2]). Supreme Court granted the motion (2015 NY Slip Op 31931[U] [2015]), and plaintiffs appealed. The Appellate Division modified on the law, declaring that the assisted suicide statutes provide a valid statutory basis to prosecute physicians who provide aid-in-dying and that the statutes do not violate the State Constitution, and as so modified, affirmed (140 A.D.3d 51, 65 [1st Dept 2016]). Plaintiffs appealed to this Court as of right, pursuant to CPLR 5601 (b) (1).
On appeal, plaintiffs argue that the State's assisted suicide statutes do not prohibit aid-in-dying as a matter of law, and that the Appellate Division's "literal" interpretation of the statutes is flawed. Alternatively, plaintiffs contend that application of the assisted suicide statutes to aid-in-dying violates their equal protection and due process rights under the State Constitution.
"On a motion to dismiss pursuant to CPLR 3211, the pleading is to be afforded a liberal construction" (Leon v Martinez, 84 N.Y.2d 83, 87-88 [1994], citing CPLR 3026). "We accept the facts as alleged in the complaint as true, accord plaintiffs the benefit of every possible favorable inference, and determine only whether the facts as alleged fit within any cognizable legal theory" (id.). "[H]owever, `allegations consisting of bare legal conclusions as well as factual claims flatly contradicted by documentary evidence are not entitled to any such consideration'" (Simkin v Blank, 19 N.Y.3d 46, 52 [2012], quoting Maas v Cornell Univ., 94 N.Y.2d 87, 91 [1999]; see Connaughton v Chipotle Mexican Grill, Inc., 29 N.Y.3d 137, 141-142 [2017]).
We reject plaintiffs' argument that the lower courts improperly resolved numerous factual issues. This case involves questions of law, including: whether aid-in-dying constitutes assisted suicide within the meaning of the Penal Law; whether a competent terminally ill person has a fundamental right to physician-assisted suicide; and whether denying a competent, terminally ill patient aid-in-dying violates that patient's right to equal treatment under the law. As there are no countervailing reasonable interpretations, these questions can be decided without any factual development.
Plaintiffs initially assert that we should interpret the assisted suicide statutes to exclude physicians who provide aid-in-dying. Such a reading would run counter to our fundamental tenets of statutory construction, and would require that we read into the statutes words and meaning wholly absent from their text (see Majewski v Broadalbin-Perth Cent. School Dist., 91 N.Y.2d 577, 583 [1998]).
"The governing rule of statutory construction is that courts are obliged to interpret a statute to effectuate the intent of the Legislature, and when the statutory language is clear and unambiguous, it should be construed so as to give effect to the plain meaning of the words used" (People v Finnegan, 85 N.Y.2d 53, 58 [1995] [internal quotation marks and brackets omitted]). "[C]ourts may not reject a literal construction [of a statute] unless it is evident that a literal construction does not correctly reflect the legislative intent" (Matter of Schinasi, 277 N.Y. 252, 259 [1938]).
"Suicide" is not defined in the Penal Law, and therefore "we must give the term its ordinary and commonly understood meaning" (People v Ocasio, 28 N.Y.3d 178, 181 [2016] [internal quotation marks omitted]). Suicide has long been understood as "the act or an instance of taking one's own life voluntarily and intentionally" (Webster's Collegiate Dictionary 1249 [11th ed 2003]; see 2 Webster, An American Dictionary of the English Language [1828]). Black's Law Dictionary (10th ed 2014) defines "suicide" as "[t]he act of taking one's own life," and "assisted suicide" as "[t]he intentional act of providing a person with the medical means or the medical knowledge to commit suicide." Aid-in-dying falls squarely within the ordinary meaning of the statutory prohibition on assisting a suicide.
The assisted suicide statutes apply to anyone who assists an attempted or completed suicide. There are no exceptions, and the statutes are unqualified in scope, creating an "irrefutable inference ... that what is omitted or not included was intended to be omitted or excluded" (People v Jackson, 87 N.Y.2d 782, 788 [1996] [internal quotation marks omitted]). Furthermore, this Court previously resolved any doubt as to the scope of the ban on assisted suicide. In People v Duffy, we explained that "section 125.15 (3)'s proscription against intentionally causing or aiding a suicide applies even where the defendant is motivated by `sympathetic' concerns, such as the desire to
As written, the assisted suicide statutes apply to a physician who intentionally prescribes a lethal dosage of a drug because such act constitutes "promoting a suicide attempt" (Penal Law § 120.30) or "aid[ing] another person to commit suicide" (Penal Law § 125.15 [3]). We therefore reject plaintiffs' statutory construction claim.
Alternatively, plaintiffs claim that the assisted suicide statutes, if applied to aid-in-dying, would violate their rights under the Equal Protection and Due Process Clauses of our State Constitution. We reject those claims.
Plaintiffs allege that the assisted suicide statutes violate the State Equal Protection Clause because some, but not all, patients may hasten death by directing the withdrawal or withholding of life-sustaining medical assistance. Plaintiffs therefore contend that the criminalization of aid-in-dying discriminates unlawfully between those terminally ill patients who can choose to die by declining life-sustaining medical assistance, and those who cannot.
Our State's equal protection guarantees are coextensive with the rights protected under the Federal Equal Protection Clause (see People v Aviles, 28 N.Y.3d 497, 502 [2016]; Matter of Esler v Walters, 56 N.Y.2d 306, 313-314 [1982]). In Vacco v Quill, the United States Supreme Court held that New York State's laws banning assisted suicide do not unconstitutionally distinguish between individuals (521 U.S. 793, 797 [1997]). As the Court explained, "[e]veryone, regardless of physical condition, is entitled, if competent, to refuse unwanted lifesaving medical treatment; no one is permitted to assist a suicide. Generally speaking, laws that apply evenhandedly to all unquestionably comply with the Equal Protection Clause" (id. at 800 [internal quotation marks omitted]). The Supreme Court has not retreated from that conclusion, and we see no reason to hold otherwise.
In support of their due process argument, plaintiffs assert that their fundamental right to self-determination and to
In Washington v Glucksberg, the United States Supreme Court "examin[ed] our Nation's history, legal traditions, and practices," and concluded that "the asserted `right' to assistance in committing suicide is not a fundamental liberty interest protected by the Due Process Clause" of the Federal Constitution (521 U.S. 702, 710, 728 [1997]). We have, at times, held that our State Due Process Clause provides greater protections than its federal counterpart (see Aviles, 28 NY3d at 505), and therefore Supreme Court precedent rejecting plaintiffs' claim as a matter of federal constitutional due process is not dispositive. Accordingly, we turn to whether the right claimed here falls within the ambit of that broader state protection.
Contrary to plaintiffs' claim, we have never defined one's right to choose among medical treatments, or to refuse life-saving medical treatments, to include any broader "right to die" or still broader right to obtain assistance from another to end one's life. In Schloendorff v Society of N.Y. Hosp., we held that a surgeon who performed an operation without the patient's consent committed an assault and, in that context, we noted that "[e]very human being of adult years and sound mind has a right to determine what shall be done with [such person's] own body" (211 N.Y. 125, 129-130 [1914]). Matter of Storar likewise concerned the right to refuse life-sustaining medical treatment when the patients were not mentally competent (52 N.Y.2d 363, 377 [1981]). In Rivers v Katz, holding that involuntarily committed mental patients have a fundamental right to refuse antipsychotic medication, we concluded that a patient's right "to refuse medical treatment must be honored, even though the recommended treatment may be beneficial or even necessary to preserve the patient's life" (67 N.Y.2d 485, 492-493 [1986]).
We have consistently adopted the well-established distinction between refusing life-sustaining treatment and assisted suicide (see Matter of Bezio v Dorsey, 21 N.Y.3d 93, 103 [2013]; Matter of Fosmire v Nicoleau, 75 N.Y.2d 218, 227 [1990]; Storar, 52 NY2d at 377 n 6). The right to refuse medical intervention is at least partially rooted in notions of bodily integrity, as the right to refuse treatment is a consequence of a person's right to resist unwanted bodily invasions (see Cruzan v Director, Mo.
"[M]erely declining medical care, even essential treatment, is not considered a suicidal act" (id.). Although we do not reach the issue addressed by Judge Rivera's concurrence on this appeal, the Supreme Court has noted that "the distinction between assisting suicide and withdrawing life-sustaining treatment, a distinction widely recognized and endorsed in the medical profession and in our legal traditions, is both important and logical; it is certainly rational," and it turns on "fundamental legal principles of causation and intent" (Vacco, 521 US at 800-801). As a general matter, the law has "long used actors' intent or purpose to distinguish between two acts that may have the same result" (id. at 802; see also Bezio, 21 NY3d at 103, quoting Matter of Von Holden v Chapman, 87 A.D.2d 66, 70 [4th Dept 1982]).
The right asserted by plaintiffs is not fundamental, and therefore the assisted suicide statutes need only be rationally related to a legitimate government interest (see People v Knox, 12 N.Y.3d 60, 67 [2009]). "The rational basis test is not a demanding one" (id. at 69); rather, it is "the most relaxed and tolerant form of judicial scrutiny" (Dallas v Stanglin, 490 U.S. 19, 26 [1989]). Rational basis involves a "strong presumption" that the challenged legislation is valid, and "a party contending otherwise bears the heavy burden of showing that a statute is so unrelated to the achievement of any combination of legitimate purposes as to be irrational" (Knox at 69 [internal quotation marks omitted]). A challenged statute will survive rational basis review so long as it is "rationally related to any conceivable legitimate State purpose" (People v Walker, 81 N.Y.2d 661, 668 [1993] [citation omitted]). "Indeed, courts may even hypothesize the Legislature's motivation or possible legitimate purpose" (Affronti v Crosson, 95 N.Y.2d 713, 719 [2001] [citation omitted]). At bottom, "[t]he rational basis standard of
As to the right asserted here, the State pursues a legitimate purpose in guarding against the risks of mistake and abuse. The State may rationally seek to prevent the distribution of prescriptions for lethal dosages of drugs that could, upon fulfillment, be deliberately or accidentally misused. The State also has a significant interest in preserving life and preventing suicide, a serious public health problem (see Bezio, 21 NY3d at 104; Storar, 52 NY2d at 377; see also Glucksberg, 521 US at 729). As summarized by the Supreme Court, the State's interests in prohibiting assisted suicide include: "prohibiting intentional killing and preserving life; preventing suicide; maintaining physicians' role as their patients' healers; protecting vulnerable people from indifference, prejudice, and psychological and financial pressure to end their lives; and avoiding a possible slide towards euthanasia" (Vacco, 521 US at 808-809). These legitimate and important state interests further "satisfy the constitutional requirement that a legislative classification bear a rational relation to some legitimate end" (id. at 809).
These interests are long-standing. As the Supreme Court observed, "[t]he earliest American statute explicitly to outlaw assisting suicide was enacted in New York in 1828" (Glucksberg, 521 US at 715 [citation omitted]). New York's Task Force on Life and the Law, which was first convened in 1984, carefully studied issues surrounding physician-assisted suicide and "unanimously concluded that [l]egalizing assisted suicide and euthanasia would pose profound risks to many individuals who are ill and vulnerable" and that the "potential dangers of this dramatic change in public policy would outweigh any benefit that might be achieved" (id. at 719 [citation and internal quotation marks omitted]). The legislature has periodically examined that ban — including in recent years — and has repeatedly rejected attempts to legalize physician-assisted suicide in New York.
The legislature may conclude that those dangers can be effectively regulated and specify the conditions under which it will permit aid-in-dying. Indeed, the jurisdictions that have permitted the practice have done so only through considered legislative action (see Or Rev Stat Ann §§ 127.800-127.897 [enacted in 1997]; Wash Rev Code §§ 70.245.010-70.245.904 [enacted in 2008]; Vt Stat Ann, tit 18, ch 113 [enacted in 2013];
Our legislature has a rational basis for criminalizing assisted suicide, and plaintiffs have no constitutional right to the relief they seek herein. Accordingly, the order of the Appellate Division should be affirmed, without costs.
RIVERA, J. (concurring).
Our State and Federal Constitutions guarantee heightened due process protections against unjustified government interference with the liberty of all persons to make certain deeply personal choices (NY Const, art I, § 6; US Const 14th Amend; see also Rivers v Katz, 67 N.Y.2d 485, 492-493 [1986]; Obergefell v Hodges, 576 US ___, ___, 135 S.Ct. 2584, 2597 [2015]). This conception of liberty is grounded in notions of individual freedom, personal autonomy, dignity, and self-determination (see Rivers, 67 NY2d at 493; Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pa. v Casey, 505 U.S. 833, 857 [1992]; Lawrence v Texas, 539 U.S. 558, 562 [2003] ["Liberty presumes an autonomy of self that includes freedom of thought, belief, expression, and certain intimate conduct"]; John P. Safranek, M.D. & Stephen J. Safranek, Can the Right to Autonomy Be Resuscitated After Glucksberg?, 69 U Colo L Rev 731, 733-742
On this appeal, the plaintiffs essentially seek a declaration that mentally-competent, terminally-ill patients have an unrestricted state constitutional right to physician-prescribed medications that hasten death. I concur with the Court that this broad right as defined by plaintiffs is not guaranteed under the New York State Constitution, and that the State has compelling and legitimate interests in prohibiting unlimited and unconditional access to physician-assisted suicide.
"Death will be different for each of us. For many, the last days will be spent in physical pain and perhaps the despair that accompanies physical deterioration and a loss of control of basic bodily and mental functions. Some will seek medication to alleviate that pain and other symptoms" (Washington v Glucksberg, 521 U.S. 702, 736 [1997, O'Connor, J., concurring]). Justice O'Connor's poignant description of the end of life is familiar to plaintiffs, who included, at the time the complaint was filed, three mentally-competent adults, two of whom were terminally ill, and one of whom was being treated for cancer. These patient plaintiffs expressed a desire for more than pain management; they sought to maintain a sense of dignity, autonomy, and personal integrity in the face of death, which they claimed had been compromised by both their respective illnesses and by the State's prohibition on assisted suicide. They requested judicial recognition of a right to decide how and when to die by accessing medication that would permit each of them to put an immediate end to their respective suffering.
Two of these patient plaintiffs have since passed. When the complaint was filed, one plaintiff was 60 years old and suffered from Lou Gehrig's disease, a neurodegenerative condition without a cure. As the disease took hold, she was in constant pain and "fe[lt] trapped in a torture chamber of her own deteriorating body," fully aware of all that was transpiring to her physically and, worse yet, that the agonizing pain would persist for the rest of her days. She sought relief in the form of prescription medications that she could ingest "to achieve a peaceful death."
The other deceased patient plaintiff was 55 years old and terminally ill with acquired immune deficiency syndrome (AIDS). A regimen of several medications kept him alive. He suffered from a variety of ailments and, as a consequence, had part of his foot amputated. He developed laryngeal carcinoma, which necessitated a tracheotomy that made it difficult for him to speak. He took more than 24 medications either through his feeding tube or by injection, and required morphine for pain management. He slept 19 hours a day and spent most of his five waking hours cleaning and maintaining his feeding and
The surviving patient plaintiff is in his eighties. He developed cancer and, after surgery to remove his bladder, suffered a recurrence but is now in remission. The complaint states that he wants "to be sure that if the cancer progresses to a terminal state, and he finds himself in a dying process he determines to be unbearable, he has available to him the option of aid-in-dying."
These patient plaintiffs, joined by a group of physicians practicing end-of-life care and the nonprofit End of Life Choices New York, challenge the application of New York's Penal Law to physicians who are willing to provide mentally-competent, terminally-ill patients, like the named patient plaintiffs, with a prescription for medication that they could ingest to end their lives before they succumb to the ravages of their illnesses. These providers maintain that aid-in-dying is a medically and ethically appropriate treatment that should be legally available to patients. They are supported by several amici, including professional organizations such as the American Medical Student Association, American Medical Women's Association, American College of Legal Medicine, New York Chapter of the National Academy of Elder Law Attorneys, and amici representing several surviving family members who have witnessed the death of a loved one, and who describe the emotional impact and stress endured by the family caregivers.
The stories retold by patient plaintiffs and amici family survivors describe the painful and harrowing experiences many terminally-ill patients endure in the final stage of life. The dying process, candidly recounted, illustrates the struggle of the terminally ill to live and die on their own terms, and is a vivid reminder of the fragility of human existence. It also provides necessary context for the legal analysis.
Constitutional limits on governmental interference with individual liberty have long included protection of the fundamental right to bodily integrity (Rivers, 67 NY2d at 492; Matter of Bezio v Dorsey, 21 N.Y.3d 93, 119 [2013]; Glucksberg, 521 US at 720; Vacco v Quill, 521 U.S. 793, 807 [1997]). Courts have
Patients in New York State unquestionably have certain fundamental rights regarding medical treatment. In Rivers v Katz, this Court stated that "[i]t is a firmly established principle of the common law of New York that every individual of adult years and sound mind has a right to determine what shall be done with [such individual's] own body" (67 NY2d at 492 [internal quotation marks omitted]). The Court continued,
A few years later, this Court noted that "the State rarely acts to protect individuals from themselves, indicating that the State's interest is less substantial when there is little or no risk of direct injury to the public. This is consistent with the primary function of the State to preserve and promote liberty and the personal autonomy of the individual" (Matter of Fosmire v Nicoleau, 75 N.Y.2d 218, 227 [1990]). As such, the "fundamental common-law right [of refusing medical treatment] is coextensive with the patient's liberty interest protected by the due process clause of our State Constitution" (Rivers, 67 NY2d at 493).
While this language may seem to countenance aid-in-dying, there are important caveats. First, the right to refuse medical treatment, while fundamental, "is not absolute and in some circumstances may have to yield to superior interests of the State" (Fosmire, 75 NY2d at 226). If a challenged statute infringes on a fundamental right, "it must withstand strict
Even though this Court's precedent establishes that the right to control medical treatment generally does not extend to assisted suicide, because the criminal statutes challenged on this appeal effect a curtailment of patients' liberty, the State's prohibition must still be rationally related to a legitimate government interest (People v Knox, 12 N.Y.3d 60, 67 [2009]). The Court here highlights how the State's legitimate interest in protecting life has led it to make a rational distinction between permitting a patient to refuse life-sustaining medical treatment and a ban on assisted suicide (per curiam op at 16; see e.g. Bezio, 21 NY3d at 103). This interest extends to protecting the lives of the terminally ill, as does the rational link between this interest and prohibiting assisted suicide. There are several bases on which the State may justify prohibiting physician-assisted suicide for the terminally ill in most cases: a terminal diagnosis may be incorrect, or at least underestimate the time a patient has left; palliative care can often reduce a patient's will to die, whether caused by physical pain or depression, and thus prolong life; vulnerable, terminally-ill patients could face external influences encouraging them to hasten their deaths, such as familial or financial pressure; the fear of opening the door to voluntary and involuntary euthanasia; and, finally, the possible negative impact on the integrity and ethics of the medical profession.
I agree, on constraint of this prior case law, that the right of a patient to determine the course of medical treatment does not, in general, encompass an unrestricted right to assisted suicide, and the State's prohibition of this practice in the vast majority of situations is rationally related to its legitimate interests. Nevertheless, this conclusion does not support the
The liberty interest protected by our State Constitution is broader than the right to decline medical treatment. At its core, liberty is the right to define oneself through deeply personal choices that form a lifetime of human experience (Casey, 505 US at 851; Rivers, 67 NY2d at 493). As we have stated "to preserve and promote liberty and the personal autonomy of the individual" is "the primary function of the State" (Fosmire, 75 NY2d at 227).
An individual's interests in autonomy and freedom are not less substantial when facing the choice of how to bear the suffering and physical pain of a terminal illness at the end of life. Self-determination includes the freedom to make decisions about how to die just as surely as it includes decision-making about life's most private matters — e.g. sexuality, marriage, procreation, and child-rearing — all choices that reflect personal beliefs and desires (see e.g. Lawrence, 539 US at 567; Matter of Brooke S.B. v Elizabeth A.C.C., 28 N.Y.3d 1, 26 [2016]). As the United States Supreme Court has recognized, "[t]he choice between life and death is a deeply personal decision of obvious and overwhelming finality" (Cruzan, 497 US at 281).
For the terminally-ill patient who is experiencing intractable pain and suffering that cannot be adequately alleviated by palliative care, plaintiffs and amici affirm that the ability to control the end stage of the dying process and achieve a peaceful death may lead to a renewed sense of autonomy and freedom.
Certainly, the State may "stay[ ] its hand" by doing nothing to assist a terminally-ill patient, thus letting the dying process take its natural course (Fosmire, 75 NY2d at 227). However, this is not the approach chosen by the State of New York. The reality is that the State already permits a patient to choose medical measures that hasten death in ways that require active, deliberate assistance of a physician. These measures are not passive. For example, the State permits the turning off of ventilators, the removal of breathing tubes, and the removal of intravenous life-sustaining nourishment and medications, even when the physician and patient know this will lead rapidly to certain death. As such, the State currently allows a physician, with a patient or a guardian's informed consent, and in the exercise of the physician's professional judgment, to affirmatively assist in bringing about a terminally-ill patient's death (see Public Health Law §§ 2994-e [1]; 2994-f [1]).
These processes are widely considered appropriate and humane end-of-life treatments that recognize the dignity of the individual patient. The justifications for allowing a physician to take active steps to precipitate a patient's death were powerfully noted in 2010, in the context of changes to the Public Health Law that now allows guardians of mentally-incompetent patients to withdraw or withhold life-sustaining treatments. Supporters of the bill wrote that,
The Assembly Memorandum in Support described the legislation as necessary because mentally-incompetent patients "may linger, through unnecessary medical intervention, in a state of irrevocable anguish," and "are, as a class, uniquely disqualified from health care rights essential to the humane and dignified treatment to which every other citizen is entitled" (Mem in Support of 2001 NY Assembly Bill A8466D).
Plaintiffs and amici Surviving Family Members similarly describe how terminally-ill patients, deprived of a legal path to bring about a death in line with their wishes, suffer excruciatingly through the final moments of their lives as their loved ones and caregivers watch helplessly. The complaint, plaintiffs' affidavits, and amici briefs are filled with accounts of patients who would have chosen aid-in-dying if the option were available. One account describes an elderly man whose bones were so riddled with cancer they would spontaneously break, even when he was lying in bed without bearing weight. Despite receiving opioids and other medications around the clock, he found his pain and suffering unbearable. He wanted to know his options for a peaceful death and the only option the physician was able to offer was for him to voluntarily stop eating and drinking. Another describes a man suffering from a degenerative motor neuron disease who, eight years after diagnosis, was wheelchair bound, had lost control of his bladder and bowels, as well as the ability to cough up food caught in his lungs, experienced his limbs atrophy, and "[e]verything which he had previously identified as degrading about dying." Ultimately he too chose to stop eating and drinking. He remained conscious during the 12 days that followed until his death, at one point developing terminal agitation that caused "sudden uncontrollable fits of yelling and violent thrashing" that led to him being strapped to his bed.
Apart from the fact that the State permits these non-passive actions to hasten death for the terminally ill, the State's interest in prohibiting aid-in-dying for this particular subgroup of patients is further weakened by its sanctioning of terminal sedation. This end-of-life treatment consists of the intravenous administration of sedatives and pain medication, often coupled with the withholding of nutrition and hydration, to a terminally-ill patient (Johannes J.M. van Delden, Terminal Sedation: Source of a Restless Ethical Debate, 33 [4] J Med Ethics 187, 187 [2007]). In 2003, the American Medical Association
For this subgroup of terminally-ill patients, the State recognizes this as a lawful means to end life.
The State and my colleagues rely on an analysis of physician intent to differentiate aid-in-dying from terminal sedation and
Moreover, this intent-based analysis fails even on its own terms. Simply put, it is impossible, as a practical matter, to distinguish between these various end-of-life practices based on a third party's state of mind. When a physician removes a patient from a life-sustaining apparatus, or declines to administer life-saving procedures, the physician's intent, in accord with the wishes of the patient, is to precipitate the death of the patient. A physician who complies with a patient's constitutionally protected choice to forgo life-sustaining treatment knows that when a ventilator is withdrawn, for example, the patient will soon die.
Even the primary distinction cited by the State and my colleagues does not hold in all cases because, as the State concedes, the drugs involved in terminal sedation are known to cause a patient's death in certain cases. A physician providing this medical option knows very well about the potential immediate consequence and must forewarn the patient (see The AMA Code of Medical Ethics' Opinions on Sedation at the End of Life at 428). Furthermore, while sedation may be necessary to alleviate a patient's pain, the withdrawal of nourishment, which forms part of the treatment, can only serve to bring about death (see David Orentlicher, The Supreme Court and Terminal Sedation: Rejecting Assisted Suicide, Embracing Euthanasia, 24 Hastings Const LQ 947, 957 [Summer 1997]). Resolution of the constitutional question requires consideration of the patient's rights; not a speculative exploration of the physician's intent.
Terminal sedation is intended to initiate what must be described for what it is: a slow-acting lethal process. While it may fall under the umbrella of palliative care (see Glucksberg, 521 US at 737-738 [O'Connor, J., concurring]), terminal sedation is not solely a method of pain management but is instead a procedure that hastens the inevitable death of the patient. It places the patient in a condition where choosing to struggle against death is no longer possible. It facilitates the patient's choice to end life.
If terminally-ill patients may exercise their liberty interest by choosing to be terminally sedated, the State has no compelling rationale, or even a rational interest, in refusing a mentally-competent, terminally-ill patient who is in the final stage of life the choice of a less intrusive option — access to aid-in-dying — which may better comport with the patient's autonomy and dignity. It is also an option which lessens the time patients and their families are forced to wait for the inevitable — often by no more than days and possibly much less.
Concerns about allowing aid-in-dying for the subgroup I have identified are misplaced. Consider, first, the State's interest in preserving life. Admittedly, the State has compelling interests that justify prohibiting assisted suicide as a general matter,
Nor does the State's general interest in preventing suicide and avoiding misdiagnosis outweigh the liberty interests in aid-in-dying for mentally-competent, terminally-ill patients facing imminent, agonizing death. The State's interests for this group of patients are not comparable to cases involving persons without terminal illnesses who are able to manage their illness and its debilitating effects, or those who for any number of personal reasons do not want to hasten death with a lethal prescription. There is no possibility of an erroneous terminal diagnosis for these patients as aid-in-dying would only be available in the last stage of life, when the end is imminent and certain. The fear that allowing aid-in-dying will result in patient coercion or be the first step to government-sanctioned euthanasia is as misplaced as the notion that terminal sedation inevitably leads to government-sanctioned euthanasia.
The State's argument that aid-in-dying would make it more difficult to ensure adequate medical treatment for those with untreated pain and depression is a valid interest in support of the State's prohibition on physician-assisted suicide as a general matter. However, it does not outweigh the interests of the terminally ill for whom pain treatment is inadequate and whose choice is not motivated by depression and helplessness, but by the desire to exercise autonomy to achieve a peaceful death, one that honors individuality and dignity (see Glucksberg, 521 US at 746-747 [Stevens, J., concurring]). Nor can it be said to be rational when the State already permits terminal sedation.
The State's other argument, that aid-in-dying undermines the integrity and ethics of the medical profession as it is incompatible with the physician's role as a healer,
In addition to the interests asserted by the State, my colleagues "hypothesize" an additional concern in avoiding misuse of a patient's dosage (per curiam op at 15, 16). Yet, the risk of the drugs involved in aid-in-dying being "deliberately or accidentally misused" is no more than with any other drug with the potential to cause severe injury or death that a physician may legally prescribe (see Office of New York State Comptroller, Prescription Opioid Abuse and Heroin Addiction in New York State [June 2016], available at https://www.osc.state.ny.us/press/releases/june16/heroin_and_opioids.pdf [accessed Aug. 29, 2017], cached at http://www.nycourts.gov/reporter/webdocs/heroin_and_opioids.pdf). At most, this simply shows that the State may regulate this area, as other states have done.
"[I]t is the province of the Judicial branch to define, and safeguard, rights provided by the New York State Constitution, and order redress for violation of them" (Campaign for Fiscal Equity v State of New York, 100 N.Y.2d 893, 925 [2003]). Although a liberty interest is at stake here, the Court implies
Mentally-competent, terminally-ill patients, with no cure or recourse other than inadequate pain management or palliative sedation to unconsciousness, and who face certain, imminent, excruciating death, are situated quantitatively and qualitatively differently from other individuals, even others living with terminal illnesses. State interests that animate the prohibition on physician aid-in-dying for these patients are diminished as death draws near and ultimately are outweighed by these patients' liberty interest and extant rights to self-determination and bodily integrity. The compelling state interests that bar physician-assisted suicide in general are not, for this group, dispositive. When the State already permits physicians to instigate other processes that precipitate death, there is no compelling basis for depriving such patients of an option that can better comport with their sense of dignity, control, and independence. Our State Constitution protects the rights of these terminally-ill patients to make the deeply personal choice of how they define and experience their final moments.
FAHEY, J. (concurring).
Experience teaches us that arguably benign policies can lead to unanticipated results. I write separately to expand on certain risks that would be associated with legalizing physician-assisted suicide in New York and that justify its prohibition.
Several significant rationales exist for criminalizing physician-assisted suicide, each of which would constitute a legitimate legislative purpose for the statute challenged here. The per curiam opinion, which I join, outlines many of these legitimate government interests (see per curiam op at 16; see also Washington v Glucksberg, 521 U.S. 702, 728-735 [1997] [holding that Washington State's then-ban on assisted suicide did not violate substantive due process under the Fourteenth Amendment of the Federal Constitution]).
I begin by discussing matters of terminology in regard to physician-assisted dying and the legal landscape in the United States. Physician-assisted suicide, the topic of this appeal, differs conceptually from euthanasia. In euthanasia, a physician brings about the death of a patient, whereas, in physician-assisted suicide, it is the patient who kills himself or herself, with the assistance of a physician. The common thread, more significant than the conceptual difference, is the use of a lethal dosage of medication intended to end the patient's life.
In the United States, physician-assisted suicide has been legalized and is regulated in Oregon (see Or Rev Stat Ann §§ 127.800-127.897 [enacted in 1997]); Washington (see Wash Rev Code §§ 70.245.010-70.245.904 [enacted in 2008]); Vermont (see Vt Stat Ann tit 18, ch 113 [enacted in 2013]); California (see End of Life Option Act, Cal Health & Safety Code part 1.85 [enacted in 2015]); Colorado (see Colo Rev Stat §§ 25-48-101 — 25-48-123 [enacted in 2016]); and the District of Columbia (see DC Act 21-577 [enacted in 2016]). Each of these jurisdictions expressly permits physician-assisted suicide by statute,
By contrast, euthanasia is legal in no jurisdiction in the United States. Here, "euthanasia" refers to active euthanasia, i.e., the intentional killing of a patient, motivated by the physician's concern for the patient's suffering or "indignity." This concept of euthanasia does not include practices — sometimes referred to as passive euthanasia but more often
I respectfully disagree with Judge Rivera's view that the difference between palliative sedation and physician-assisted suicide "is not meaningful in the constitutional sense" (Rivera, J., concurring op at 27). Instead, I would follow the Supreme Court's analysis in Vacco v Quill (521 U.S. 793 [1997]).
Finally, there is an important distinction between voluntary and non-voluntary euthanasia. Voluntary euthanasia is euthanasia in accordance with the request of a mentally competent patient. Non-voluntary euthanasia is euthanasia performed on someone who, because of a factor such as infancy, mental incompetence, coma, etc., is not able to choose euthanasia and has never recorded a directive expressing his or her will in regard to euthanasia. Involuntary euthanasia, not implicated here, would be euthanasia performed on a person who is able to give consent, but has not done so, either because the person was not asked or because he or she withheld consent (see generally L.W. Sumner, Assisted Death: A Study in Ethics and Law at 17).
The practice of physician-assisted suicide and euthanasia in the Netherlands provides us with a disturbing preview of what it would be rational to expect upon legalization. In what follows, I concentrate on that country, which has the longest history of socially accepted euthanasia, while adding comments on other jurisdictions that have legalized euthanasia or physician-assisted suicide. It will be clear from the foregoing section that the practices to be discussed below are euthanasia and physician-assisted suicide, not palliative sedation or removal of a patient from life support or other treatment.
In the Netherlands in 2002, the Termination of Life on Request and Assisted Suicide (Review Procedures) Act was enacted to legalize and regulate long-standing preexisting practices of physician-assisted suicide and voluntary euthanasia. Under that statute, a physician may end the life of a patient who is experiencing unbearable suffering without hope of relief, at the patient's explicit request, either by administering a lethal dosage of medication (euthanasia) or by prescribing a
In 2015, euthanasia and physician-assisted suicide accounted for 5,516 reported deaths in the Netherlands, almost four percent of all deaths in the country, estimated at around 140,000 per annum (see Regional Euthanasia Review Committees, Annual Report 2015 at 16, https://english. euthanasiecommissie.nl/documents/publications/annual-reports/2002/annual-reports/annual-reports [accessed Aug. 21, 2017]). The proportion of deaths attributed to euthanasia and physician-assisted suicide had more than doubled over 10 years (see Regional Euthanasia Review Committees, Annual Report 2005 at 2, https://english.euthanasiecommissie.nl/documents/publications/annual-reports/2002/annual-reports/annual-reports [accessed Aug. 21, 2017] [1,933 cases of euthanasia and assisted suicide were reported in 2005]).
The most immediately striking aspect of end-of-life decision-making in the Netherlands is that no legal or ethical distinction is drawn between physician-assisted suicide and euthanasia. Similarly, physician-assisted suicide and euthanasia were made legal at the same time as one another in both Belgium (2002) and Luxembourg (2009). In Canada, a 2015 Supreme Court of Canada decision striking down a prohibition on assisted suicide led to a June 2016 law legalizing both "the prescribing or providing by a medical practitioner or nurse practitioner of a substance to a person, at their request, so that they may self-administer the substance and in doing so cause their own death" (physician-assisted suicide) and "the administering by a medical practitioner or nurse practitioner of a substance to a person, at their request, that causes their death" (euthanasia) (Statutes of Canada 2016, Bill C-14, An Act to amend the Criminal Code and to make related amendments to other Acts [medical assistance in dying], available at http://www.parl.ca/Content/Bills/421/Government/C-14/C-14_4/C-14_4.PDF [accessed Aug. 21, 2017], cached at http://www.nycourts.gov/reporter/webdocs/C-14_4.pdf; see also https://openparliament.ca/bills/42-1/C-14 [accessed Aug. 21, 2017]). The movement from allowing physician-assisted suicide to permitting euthanasia is facile; indeed, it apparently has not
It is true, as I have already noted, that in the United States active euthanasia is nowhere legal, whereas physician-assisted suicide is permitted in six states and the District of Columbia. I am not convinced, however, that this state of affairs will last. The evidence from the Netherlands, Belgium, Luxembourg, and Canada suggests it will not. Moreover, the line between physician-assisted suicide and euthanasia is difficult to defend. If a person has the statutory or other right to physician-assisted suicide, does she lose the right to die if she suddenly becomes too physically weak to self-administer lethal prescribed drugs? "[T]his would arguably amount to discrimination based upon physical disability" (Sampson v State, 31 P.3d 88, 97 [Alaska 2001] [upholding as constitutional a criminal statute prohibiting intentionally aiding another person to commit suicide]; see also e.g. Dan W. Brock, Voluntary Active Euthanasia, 22 Hastings Ctr Rep 10, 10 [1992]). In practice, it appears that in Oregon a feeding tube is sometimes used to enable a patient who wishes to commit suicide using prescription medication, but has lost mobility, to ingest the lethal prescription (see Disability Rights Education & Defense Fund, Some Oregon and Washington State Assisted Suicide Abuses and Complications, Self-Administration, https://dredf.org/public-policy/assisted-suicide/some-oregon-assisted-suicide-abuses-and-complications/ [accessed Aug. 21, 2017], cached at http://www.nycourts.gov/reporter/webdocs/some-oregon-and-washington.pdf).
Indeed, this concern about the transition from physician-assisted suicide to euthanasia was recognized by the United States Supreme Court, which observed that "in some instances, the patient may be unable to self-administer the drugs and... administration by the physician ... may be the only way the patient may be able to receive them," and that "not only physicians, but also family members and loved ones, will inevitably participate in assisting suicide. Thus, it turns out that what is couched as a limited right to `physician-assisted suicide' is likely, in effect, a much broader license, which could prove extremely difficult to police and contain" (Glucksberg, 521 US at 733 [internal quotation marks and citations omitted]). Justice Souter expanded on the point, noting that
Based on the current experience in the Netherlands, an expansion from physician-assisted suicide, by a patient taking a prescription of fatal drugs, to euthanasia, by a nurse or physician administering a prescription of fatal drugs, seems all but inevitable. Certainly the fear of that expansion, if physician-assisted suicide were legalized in New York, is reasonable.
The Netherlands has displayed another very disturbing trend: the countenancing of both voluntary euthanasia and non-voluntary euthanasia. A study conducted in 2005 revealed that 2,410 people in the Netherlands, 1.8% of all deaths in the Netherlands that year, died as a result of voluntary euthanasia or physician-assisted suicide,
A similar study of euthanasia and physician-assisted suicide in Belgium revealed a large proportion of patients who received euthanasia without an explicit request, some 32% of those who received euthanasia (see Kenneth Chambaere et al., Physician-Assisted Deaths under the Euthanasia Law in Belgium: A Population-Based Survey, 182 Canadian Med Ass'n J 895, 896, 897 [2010] [Table 1], available at http://www.cmaj.ca/content/182/9/895 [accessed Aug. 21, 2017]). Typically, in Belgian cases of non-voluntary euthanasia, the patient is in a coma or suffering from dementia, and relatives or other caregivers are consulted in advance regarding the euthanasia (see id. at 898-899).
In studying the modern experience in the Benelux nations, we are, of course, not facing government-sanctioned forced euthanasia. The decision-makers in non-voluntary euthanasia may be well-meaning. Such consultation, however, does not render the euthanasia voluntary, and indeed brings to mind the necessity of ensuring that decision-making about ending the lives of vulnerable, terminally ill people is not entrusted entirely to those who have the financial and emotional burden of caring for them.
I am not suggesting that the legalization of voluntary euthanasia, in a society such as the Netherlands in which it was already widely practiced, necessarily increases the rate of non-voluntary euthanasia. It may not invariably do so (see Agnes van der Heide et al., End-of-Life Practices in the Netherlands under the Euthanasia Act). My point is simply that physician-assisted suicide and euthanasia are inevitably accompanied by instances of non-voluntary euthanasia, so that it is rational to predict that endorsement of physician-assisted suicide will lead to occurrences of non-voluntary euthanasia.
There is also a reasonable concern that a descent from voluntary euthanasia and physician-assisted suicide to non-voluntary euthanasia would be an especial risk in vulnerable and disadvantaged parts of society. In 1994, the New York State Task Force on Life and the Law "unanimously recommend[ed]
As the Task Force observed,
It is true that research from Oregon suggests that such fears of non-voluntary euthanasia of the vulnerable have not yet come to pass. "[R]ates of assisted dying in Oregon ... showed no evidence of heightened risk for the elderly, women, the uninsured..., people with low educational status, the poor, the physically disabled or chronically ill, minors, people with psychiatric illnesses including depression, or racial or ethnic minorities, compared with background populations" (Margaret P. Battin et al., Legal Physician-Assisted Dying in Oregon and the Netherlands: Evidence Concerning the Impact on Patients in "Vulnerable" Groups, 33 J Med Ethics 591, 591 [2007], available at https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC2652799 [accessed Aug. 21, 2017]). Yet the experiment with physician-assisted suicide on the West Coast is still young, and the Dutch experience supports the rationality of such fears.
Another part of society that could be at significant long-term risk is the community of people who are disabled. The Disability Rights Amici argue that while the plaintiffs
For the many members of the disabled community who are not terminally ill, the "indignities" that plaintiffs wish to avoid are
A disability does not deprive life of integrity or value. There is no lack of nobility or true dignity in being dependent on others. The natural developments of old age and final illness are dependence and waning consciousness. Many disabilities come with similar challenges. It would be a profound mistake to equate limits imposed on a person's life with the conclusion that such a life has no value.
Last year, the American Psychiatric Association (APA) stated its official policy on physician-assisted suicide or euthanasia of psychiatric patients: "a psychiatrist should not prescribe or administer any intervention to a non-terminally ill person for the purpose of causing death" (APA, Position Statement on Medical Euthanasia [Dec. 2016], available at https://www.psychiatry.org/home/policy-finder [accessed Aug. 21, 2017]). At the time, a member of the APA's ethics committee stated that he feared that Canada and the jurisdictions in the United States that have legalized physician-assisted suicide are headed in the same direction as the Netherlands and Belgium. "So far, no other country that has implemented physician-assisted suicide has been able to constrain its application solely to the terminally ill, eventually including non-terminal patients as legally eligible as well ... This is when psychiatric patients start to be included" (Michael Cook, American Psychiatric Association Takes Historic Stand on Assisted Suicide and Euthanasia, BioEdge: bioethics news from around the world, Dec. 16, 2016, available at https://www.bioedge.org/bioethics/american-psychiatric-association-takes-historic-stand-on-assisted-suicide-a/12137 [accessed Aug. 21, 2017], cached at http://www.nycourts.gov/reporter/webdocs/bioedge.pdf).
The experience of euthanasia in the Netherlands amply justifies this assertion. Euthanasia and physician-assisted suicide in the Netherlands have not been limited to those whose pain is physical. As long as "the patient's suffering is unbearable and without prospect of improvement" (Government of the Netherlands, Is Euthanasia Allowed?), a person whose illness is psychiatric may request and receive euthanasia or commit
A 2016 survey of the euthanasia and physician-assisted suicide of 66 patients with psychiatric suffering in the Netherlands from 2011 to 2014 found that in most cases the patient's primary psychiatric condition was a depressive disorder (Scott Y.H. Kim et al., Euthanasia and Assisted Suicide of Patients with Psychiatric Disorders in the Netherlands 2011 to 2014, 73 JAMA Psychiatry 362, 364 [2016], available at http://jamanetwork.com/journals/jamapsychiatry/fullarticle/2491354 [accessed Aug. 21, 2017]), ranging from "patients with chronic, severe, difficult-to-treat depressions" to a woman who had lost her husband and found life as a widow "meaningless" but "did not feel depressed at all" and "ate, drank, and slept well ... followed the news and undertook activities" (id.).
The same survey noted that most of the patients felt "social isolation or loneliness," including one who believed "that she had had a life without love and therefore had no right to exist" and "an utterly lonely man whose life had been a failure" (id. at 365). The authors of the survey concluded that the patients receiving euthanasia or physician-assisted suicide "are mostly women ... with various chronic psychiatric conditions, accompanied by personality disorders, significant physical problems, and social isolation or loneliness" (id. at 367). It is
Recently, the Netherlands has shown signs of taking a new path down the slope that began with physician-assisted suicide and euthanasia of the terminally ill. In 2016, the Health Minister defended a proposed law allowing healthy older people to seek euthanasia if they feel that they "do not have the possibility to continue life in a meaningful way, ... are struggling with the loss of independence and reduced mobility, ... have a sense of loneliness, partly because of the loss of loved ones, and ... are burdened by general fatigue, deterioration and loss of personal dignity" (Dan Bilefsky & Christopher F. Schuetze, Dutch Law Would Allow Assisted Suicide for Healthy Older People, NY Times, Oct. 14, 2016 at A5, available at https://www.nytimes.com/2016/10/14/world/europe/dutch-law-would-allow-euthanasia-for-healthy-elderly-people.html?_r=0 [accessed Aug. 21, 2017]). The proposed law essentially would allow people who are tired of life to end their lives.
Notably, the authors of the 2016 survey observe that the requirement that there be no "prospect of improvement" has proved controversial when the people seeking euthanasia are psychiatric patients. The survey authors found that almost one third of the patients had initially been refused euthanasia or physician-assisted suicide and that almost one quarter of the cases "engendered disagreements among the physicians involved" (Scott Y.H. Kim et al., Euthanasia and Assisted Suicide of Patients with Psychiatric Disorders in the Netherlands 2011 to 2014, 73 JAMA Psychiatry at 367 [emphasis added]). They noted "the ... complicated determinations of medical futility that must incorporate patients' treatment refusals in the context of less-than-certain prognosis even among persons with treatment-resistant depression" (id.). Such disagreements are telling.
Of course, in the United States jurisdictions that permit physician-assisted suicide, the practice is currently limited to patients who have six months to live. The descent down the slippery slope in the Netherlands, however, verifies the fear that jurisdictions in this country will find it difficult to limit the application of physician-assisted dying to the terminally ill.
Perhaps most disturbingly, the Dutch practice of legalized euthanasia and physician-assisted suicide has quickly been extended to young children. In the Netherlands, children
Recently, the Dutch Pediatric Association has called for the age limit of 12 years old to be eliminated, so that "each child's ability to ask to die [w]ould be evaluated on a case-by-case basis" (Dutch Paediatricians: Give Terminally Ill Children under 12 the Right to Die, The Guardian, June 19, 2015, available at https://www.theguardian.com/society/2015/jun/19/terminally-ill-children-right-to-die-euthanasia-netherlands [accessed Aug. 21, 2017], cached at http://www.nycourts.gov/reporter/webdocs/dutch_paediatricians.pdf).
This would put the Netherlands in line with Belgium. In 2014, a dozen years after the 2002 Belgian Act on Euthanasia legalized euthanasia and physician-assisted suicide for adults suffering from constant, unbearable suffering (whether physical or psychiatric) that cannot be alleviated, Belgium legalized euthanasia by lethal injection for similarly situated children, of any age, provided they possess "the capacity of discernment" and there is parental consent (Belgium Passes Law Extending Euthanasia to Children of All Ages, The Guardian, Feb. 13, 2014, available at https://www.theguardian.com/world/2014/feb/13/belgium-law-extends-euthanasia-children-all-ages [accessed Aug. 21, 2017], cached at http://www.nycourts.gov/reporter/webdocs/belgium-law-extend.pdf).
The expansion of euthanasia to children needs little commentary. Our society recognizes that minors "are in the earlier
The evidence from other countries is that legitimating physician-assisted suicide can lead to the acceptance of non-voluntary euthanasia and to the extension of physician-assisted suicide to patients, such as those suffering from depression, who are not terminally ill. Such developments, valuing the avoidance of suffering above all virtues of endurance and hope for the future, should be intensely disturbing to all of us. The risk of facilitating such a bleak prospect is a rational justification for New York's prohibition of assisted suicide.
GARCIA, J. (concurring).
I agree with and join in the Court's holdings that Penal Law §§ 120.30 and 125.15 (3) encompass aid-in-dying (per curiam op at section III), and that the statutes do not violate plaintiffs' right to equal protection under the New York State Constitution (per curiam op at section IV [A]). To the extent plaintiffs' allegations overlap with those asserted in Washington v Glucksberg (521 U.S. 702 [1997]), I also agree with the Court's conclusion that, here, our State Due Process Clause is no broader than its federal counterpart and, therefore, plaintiffs' claims must fail. I write separately because I believe the Court should go further; to the extent plaintiffs' assert a "more particularized" challenge to the assisted suicide statutes (id. at 750 [Stevens, J., concurring]), I would expressly reach — and reject — those claims.
In support of their due process claim, plaintiffs argue that the assisted suicide statutes burden a fundamental right and
In Washington v Glucksberg, the Supreme Court rejected the plaintiffs' due process challenge to Washington's prohibition against "caus[ing]" or "aid[ing]" a suicide (521 U.S. 702, 705-706 [1997]). There, the Court determined that the "right" to assistance in committing suicide asserted by the plaintiffs was "not a fundamental liberty interest protected by the Due Process Clause" of the Federal Constitution (id. at 728). Because Washington's ban on assisted suicide was "at least reasonably related" to a number of "important and legitimate" state interests, the Court concluded that it survived rational basis review and that it did not violate the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment (id. at 735).
Addressing the scope of its ruling, the Court carefully framed the issue presented: "It is ... the [lower] court's holding that Washington's physician-assisted suicide statute is unconstitutional as applied to the class of terminally ill, mentally competent patients that is before us today" (id. at 709 n 6 [citation and internal quotation marks omitted]).
The same conclusion is warranted under our State Due Process Clause.
In general, our Court "use[s] the same analytical framework as the Supreme Court in considering due process cases"
In Glucksberg, the Supreme Court began by considering our Nation's "history, legal traditions, and practices" with respect to aid-in-dying, emphasizing New York's pivotal role at the forefront of legislative efforts to punish assisted suicide (Glucksberg, 521 US at 710-719). Like most states, New York has "consistently condemned, and continue[s] to prohibit, assisting suicide" (id. at 719). The earliest American statute explicitly outlawing assisted suicide was enacted in New York nearly two centuries ago, with many states and territories later following New York's example (see id. at 715). In 1857, a New York commission led by Dudley Field drafted a criminal code that prohibited "aiding" a suicide (id.). The Field Code was adopted in New York in 1881, and "its language served as a model for several other western States' statutes" (id.). The language of the prohibition remained largely unchanged until 1965, when Penal Law §§ 120.30 and 125.15 (3) were enacted as part of a "new Penal Law" that "reorganize[d] and modernize[d] penal provisions proscribing conduct which has traditionally been considered criminal" (Governor's Approval Mem, Bill Jacket, L 1965, ch 1030 at 34-35, 1965 NY Legis Ann at 530).
Since then, the statutes have been repeatedly reexamined, including by New York's Task Force on Life and the Law, which studied physician-assisted suicide and unanimously concluded that the "potential dangers" of such a "dramatic change in public policy would outweigh any benefit that might be achieved" (Glucksberg at 719 [citation omitted]). Despite repeated attempts to legalize aid-in-dying in New York, the legislature has not retreated from its prohibition.
To be sure, "the common law of New York" recognizes a patient's right "to determine what shall be done with his own body and to control the course of his medical treatment" (Rivers v Katz, 67 N.Y.2d 485, 492 [1986] [citation and internal quotation marks omitted]; see also Schloendorff v Society of N.Y. Hosp., 211 N.Y. 125, 129-130 [1914]). In Matter of Storar, we explicitly recognized a competent patient's right to refuse medical treatment, even where the treatment may be necessary to preserve the patient's life (52 N.Y.2d 363, 376 [1981]).
But we have never defined this fundamental right to encompass the broad "right to die" that plaintiffs seek; rather, we have consistently reaffirmed the widely-recognized distinction between refusing life-sustaining treatment and assisted suicide (per curiam op at 14, citing Matter of Bezio v Dorsey, 21 N.Y.3d 93, 103 [2013]; Matter of Fosmire, 75 NY2d at 227; Storar, 52 NY2d at 377 n 6). This distinction "comports with fundamental legal principles of causation and intent" (Vacco v Quill, 521 U.S. 793, 801 [1997]). When a patient refuses life-sustaining treatment and succumbs to illness, the cause of death is the underlying disease. By contrast, when a lethal medication is ingested, the cause of death is not the pre-existing illness, but rather, the prescribed medication. In addition, a physician who withdraws treatment or administers terminal sedation does not intend to kill the patient, though that may be the eventual result. Rather, the physician intends only to respect the patient's right to die naturally and free from intrusion, and to alleviate any pain or discomfort that may accompany that decision. A physician who provides aid-in-dying, however, indisputably intends for his or her actions to directly cause the patient's death; that is the very purpose of the lethal prescription.
New York's "consistent and almost universal tradition" has "long rejected the asserted right, and continues to explicitly reject it today" (Glucksberg, 521 US at 723). The assisted suicide
Because the assisted suicide statutes do not implicate a fundamental right, they need only be "rationally related to any conceivable legitimate State purpose" (People v Walker, 81 N.Y.2d 661, 668 [1993] [citation omitted]). As the rational basis test is "the most relaxed and tolerant form of judicial scrutiny," plaintiffs bear the "heavy burden" of defeating the "strong presumption" that the statutes are valid (Dallas v Stanglin, 490 U.S. 19, 26 [1989]). Even if the State could "better promote and protect" its interests "through regulation, rather than prohibition, of physician-assisted suicide," our inquiry is "limited to the question whether the State's prohibition is rationally related to legitimate state interests" (Glucksberg, 521 US at 728 n 21). So long as this basic requirement is satisfied, we "need not weigh exactingly the relative strengths" of the various competing interests (id. at 735).
A number of legitimate state interests support the assisted suicide statutes. First, the State has a significant interest in preserving life and preventing suicide (per curiam op at 16; see also Storar, 52 NY2d at 377; Bezio, 21 NY3d at 104; Glucksberg, 521 US at 729). Suicide presents a "serious public-health problem," often plaguing those who "suffer from depression or other mental disorders" — conditions that may be difficult to diagnose (Glucksberg, 521 US at 730 [citation omitted]). The availability of assisted suicide would therefore undermine the State's interest in preventing suicide in cases involving, for instance, untreated depression, coercion, or improperly managed pain.
The State has also asserted a valid interest in preserving the integrity of the medical profession. A number of medical professionals — including the American Medical Association, the Medical Society of the State of New York, the New York State Hospice and Palliative Care Association, and the New York State Task Force on Life and the Law — expressly reject physician-assisted suicide as an accepted medical practice (e.g. brief for the 39 Physicians at 4-13). Many believe that "physician-assisted suicide is fundamentally incompatible with the physician's role as healer," and could "undermine the trust that is essential to the doctor-patient relationship by blurring the time-honored line between healing and harming" (Glucksberg, 521 US at 731 [citations, brackets and internal quotation marks omitted]).
The Supreme Court has recognized that these, and other, "valid and important public interests" support New York's assisted suicide statutes (Vacco, 521 US at 809). Each of these state interests, by itself, "easily satisf[ies] the constitutional requirement that a legislative classification bear a rational relation to some legitimate end" (id.); collectively, they overwhelmingly substantiate the legislature's prohibition of aid-in-dying. Accordingly, as in Glucksberg, the assisted suicide statutes do not violate our State Due Process Clause either on their face or "as applied to competent, terminally ill adults who
Despite the breadth of Glucksberg's holding, plaintiffs — and others — suggest that the Supreme Court left open the possibility that some other plaintiff, under some other set of circumstances, might successfully assert an as-applied challenge to an assisted suicide ban (see Glucksberg, 521 US at 738-752 [Stevens, J., concurring]; see also per curiam op at 15; Morris v Brandenburg, 2016-NMSC-027, ¶ 30, 376 P.3d 836, 847 [2016]; James Bopp, Jr. & Richard E. Coleson, Three Strikes: Is An Assisted Suicide Right Out?, 15 Issues L & Med 3, 35-36 [1999]; Adam J. Cohen, The Open Door: Will the Right to Die Survive Washington v. Glucksberg and Vacco v. Quill?, 16 In Pub Int 79, 98-107 [1997]; Physician-Assisted Suicide, 111 Hary L Rev 237, 243-245 [1997]). Although plaintiffs here assert a more particularized challenge to the assisted suicide statutes, their as-applied challenge nonetheless fails.
In Glucksberg, Justice Stevens, concurring in the judgment, asserted that the Court had conceived of the plaintiffs' claim "as a facial challenge — addressing not the application of the statute to a particular set of plaintiffs before it, but the constitutionality of the statute's categorical prohibition" against assisting a suicide (Glucksberg, 521 US at 740 [Stevens, J., concurring]). Specifically, Justice Stevens noted that all three of the terminally ill patient plaintiffs had died during the pendency of the litigation, and the Court therefore "did not have before it any individual plaintiff seeking to hasten her death or any doctor who was threatened with prosecution for assisting in the suicide of a particular patient" (id. at 739 [Stevens, J., concurring]). Accordingly, Justice Stevens contended that the Court's holding left open "the possibility that some applications of the statute might well be invalid" (id. [Stevens, J., concurring]).
Writing for the majority, Chief Justice Rehnquist conceded that the Court's opinion did not "absolutely foreclose" the possibility that "an individual plaintiff seeking to hasten her death, or a doctor whose assistance was sought, could prevail in a more particularized challenge" (id. at 735 n 24, citing id.
Plaintiffs here explicitly seek to present the "more particularized" as-applied challenge purportedly "not foreclose[d]" by Glucksberg (Glucksberg, 521 US at 739, 750 [Stevens, J., concurring]). As detailed in the complaint, plaintiffs' allegations encompass a number of diverse parties whose experiences span the myriad stages of terminal illness.
At the time the complaint was filed, plaintiffs included competent, terminally ill patients who sought "to declare unconstitutional the application of New York penal law" to their respective circumstances. These patient plaintiffs requested, among other things, the option to "ingest medications prescribed by [their] doctor[s] to achieve a peaceful death."
Plaintiffs also include a number of medical providers, including physicians whose patients "have requested" assistance to "help them die peacefully and with dignity." As alleged in the complaint, each physician plaintiff, in the course of his current medical practice, "regularly encounters mentally-competent, terminally-ill patients who have no chance of recovery and for whom medicine cannot offer any hope other than some degree of symptomatic relief." In some of those cases, "even symptomatic relief is impossible to achieve without the use of terminal sedation." An "[u]ncertainty about the application" of the assisted suicide statutes deters these medical professionals from "exercising [their] best professional judgment [to provide] aid-in-dying."
Plaintiffs' challenge, though more particularized, is not meaningfully "different" from the claims rejected in Glucksberg (521 US at 735 n 24). Given our holding that the Due Process Clause of the New York State Constitution does not provide heightened protection to the asserted liberty interest, plaintiffs must show, with respect to their as-applied challenge, that the assisted suicide statutes no longer survive rational basis review. Plaintiffs cannot make the requisite showing because, despite the uniquely compelling interests of the terminally ill "facing an impending painful death" (Rivera, J., concurring op at 23), the State's asserted interests subsist even where a patient is "in the final stage of life" (Rivera, J., concurring op at 29).
The legitimate interests advanced by the State support the assisted suicide statutes irrespective of a patient's proximity to death or eligibility for terminal sedation. For instance, the State may permissibly conclude that its interest in preserving life does not "diminish" merely because a patient's death may be "certain" or "imminent" (Rivera, J., concurring op at 18, 34). Rather, research demonstrates that "suicidal feelings in terminally ill people" are often "remediable through other means, including pain management, hospice services and counseling," notwithstanding the patient's impending or imminent death (brief for Disability Rights Amici at 21). In the State's view, this data may undermine any assurance that, in the "last stage of life," a patient's "choice is not motivated by depression and helplessness, but by the desire to exercise autonomy to achieve a peaceful death" (Rivera, J., concurring op at 30, 31).
The risk of misuse similarly persists regardless of a patient's "stage of the dying process" (Rivera, J., concurring op at 18).
Nor does the State's interest in promoting sound medical ethics dissipate as death draws near (Rivera, J., concurring op at 31-33). To the contrary, the State has asserted that the assisted suicide statutes encourage the unconditional treatment of the terminally ill and preserve the critical element of trust in a doctor-patient relationship at a time often marked by intense fear, uncertainty, and vulnerability. Even assuming this asserted rationale is "not uniformly accepted" (Rivera, J., concurring op at 31), skepticism of aid-in-dying unquestionably remains among well-regarded medical professionals, including a number of the State's amici in this case. The State is entitled to adopt this legitimate medical perspective, which, by itself, adequately substantiates the assisted suicide statutes.
In any event, the State may permissibly conclude that an absolute ban on assisted suicide is the most reliable, effective, and administrable means of protecting against its inherent dangers (per curiam op at 17; see also Glucksberg, 521 US at 731-733). Indeed, the State's legitimate interest in promoting a bright-line rule is particularly evident when considering the challenges posed by regulation. For instance, Judge Rivera's proposed rule, which would permit aid-in-dying in the "last painful stage of life," would purportedly apply only where a patient qualifies as "mentally-competent" and "terminally-ill"; where the patient is "experiencing intractable pain and suffering"; where "pain treatment is inadequate"; where death is "certain" and "imminent"; and where the patient's choice "is not motivated by depression and helplessness" (Rivera, J., concurring op at 18, 23, 24, 31, 34). But the concurrence fails to
The Due Process Clause of our State Constitution does not encompass a fundamental right to physician-assisted suicide, and the State's prohibition is rationally related to a number of legitimate government interests — interests that support the assisted suicide statutes irrespective of a patient's "stage of the dying process" (Rivera, J., concurring op at 18, 23). To the extent a hypothetical future plaintiff — presenting a "quite different" set of circumstances — might come forward, the prospect of a successful constitutional challenge is never "absolutely foreclose[d]" (Glucksberg, 521 US at 735 n 24). But in light of the Court's holding today — and our unanimous conclusion that heightened scrutiny is unwarranted — it is difficult to conceive of such a case. Plaintiffs' claims are better addressed to the legislature.
Order affirmed, without costs.