MARKMAN, J.
We granted leave to appeal to address (1) whether Miller v. Alabama, 567 U.S. ___, 132 S.Ct. 2455, 183 L.Ed.2d 407 132 S.Ct. 2455; 183 L.Ed.2d 407 (2012), should be applied retroactively — pursuant to either the federal or state test for retroactivity — to cases in which the defendant's sentence became final for purposes of direct appellate review before Miller was decided and (2) whether the Eighth Amendment of the United States Constitution or Const. 1963, art. 1, § 16 categorically bars the imposition of a life-without-parole sentence on a juvenile homicide offender. After considering these matters, we hold that the rule announced in Miller does not satisfy either the federal test for retroactivity set forth in Teague v. Lane, 489 U.S. 288, 109 S.Ct. 1060, 103 L.Ed.2d 334 (1989), or Michigan's separate and independent test for retroactivity set forth in People v. Sexton, 458 Mich. 43, 580 N.W.2d 404 (1998), and People v. Maxson, 482 Mich. 385, 759 N.W.2d 817 (2008). We further hold that neither the Eighth Amendment nor Const. 1963, art. 1, § 16 categorically bars the imposition of a life-without-parole sentence on a juvenile homicide offender.
Defendant Raymond Carp was 15 years of age when he participated in the 2006 bludgeoning and stabbing of Mary Ann McNeely in Casco Township. He was charged with first-degree murder in violation of MCL 750.316 and tried as an adult. On October 5, 2006, a St. Clair County jury convicted Carp of this offense, and in accordance with the law he was sentenced to life imprisonment without parole. Carp's conviction was subsequently affirmed by the Court of Appeals, People v. Carp, unpublished opinion per curiam of the Court of Appeals, issued December 30, 2008 (Docket No. 275084), 2008 WL
In September 2010, Carp sought to collaterally attack the constitutionality of his sentence by filing a motion for relief from judgment pursuant to MCR 6.501 et seq. The trial court denied this motion, concluding that the imposition of a mandatory sentence of life without parole on a juvenile first-degree-murder offender did not constitute cruel or unusual punishment, citing People v. Launsburry, 217 Mich.App. 358, 363-365, 551 N.W.2d 460 (1996), lv. den. 454 Mich. 883, 562 N.W.2d 203 (1997), and recon. den. 454 Mich. 883, 564 N.W.2d 900 (1997). Carp then sought leave to appeal in the Court of Appeals, which was denied on June 8, 2012. People v. Carp, unpublished order of the Court of Appeals, entered June 8, 2012 (Docket No. 307758). Seventeen days later, the United States Supreme Court issued its decision in Miller, leading Carp to move for reconsideration, and the Court of Appeals granted his motion. People v. Carp, unpublished order of the Court of Appeals, entered August 9, 2012 (Docket No. 307758). On reconsideration, the Court determined that Miller had created a "new rule" that was "procedural" in nature and therefore not subject to retroactive application under the rules set forth in Teague. People v. Carp, 298 Mich.App. 472, 511-515, 828 N.W.2d 685 (2012). The Court further held that Miller was not subject to retroactive application under Michigan's separate test for retroactivity set forth in Sexton and Maxson.
Defendant Cortez Davis, age 16 at the time of his offense, and one of his cohorts, while both brandishing firearms, accosted two individuals in Detroit for the purpose of robbery.
At sentencing, the trial court initially ruled that Michigan's statutory sentencing scheme for first-degree murder could not constitutionally be applied to juvenile homicide offenders because it was "cruel and unusual" to impose a sentence of life without parole on a juvenile who was "capable of rehabilitation." In concluding that Davis was such an individual, the court surmised that Davis's role in the commission of the offense was that of an aider and abettor, not an actual shooter. The court, however, did not make any finding concerning Davis's intentions with respect to the fleeing victim or whether
On appeal, however, the Court of Appeals reversed and remanded for resentencing pursuant to Michigan's statutory sentencing scheme, People v. Davis, unpublished order of the Court of Appeals, entered November 23, 1994 (Docket No. 176985), and at resentencing, the trial court imposed the required sentence of life without parole. Direct appellate review of defendant's conviction and sentence concluded in 2000. People v. Davis, unpublished order of the Court of Appeals, entered June 15, 2000 (Docket No. 224046).
In 2010, Davis filed his current motion for relief from judgment, contending that Graham v. Florida, 560 U.S. 48, 130 S.Ct. 2011, 176 L.Ed.2d 825 (2010), constituted a "retroactive change in the law" in that it categorically barred life-without-parole sentences for juveniles convicted of nonhomicide offenses. Concluding, however, that felony murder is in fact a "homicide offense," even when the defendant is not the actual shooter but an aider and abettor, the trial court denied this motion. The Court of Appeals denied Davis's application for leave to appeal. People v. Davis, unpublished order of the Court of Appeals, entered November 16, 2011 (Docket No. 304075). While Davis's application for leave to appeal in this Court was pending, the United States Supreme Court issued its decision in Miller. In light of Miller, Davis's case was remanded to the trial court for a determination of whether Miller applied retroactively. People v. Davis, 492 Mich. 871, 820 N.W.2d 167 (2012). On remand, the trial court concluded that Miller did apply retroactively, entitling Davis to be resentenced. The prosecutor then appealed, and the Court of Appeals reversed. People v. Davis, unpublished order of the Court of Appeals, entered January 16, 2013 (Docket No. 314080), citing Carp, 298 Mich.App. 472, 828 N.W.2d 685. Davis again sought leave to appeal in this Court, which we granted to address whether the Eighth Amendment of the United States Constitution or Const. 1963, art. 1, § 16 categorically bars imposing a sentence of life without parole on a juvenile convicted of felony murder on aiding-and-abetting grounds. People v. Davis, 495 Mich. 890, 838 N.W.2d 881 (2013).
Unlike Carp and Davis, whose sentences became final for purposes of direct review
While Eliason's appeal was pending before the Court of Appeals, Miller was decided. In assessing the effect of Miller on Michigan's sentencing scheme for juvenile first-degree-murder offenders, the Court of Appeals held that a trial court must as a result of Miller perform an individualized sentencing analysis based upon the factors identified in Miller. People v. Eliason, 300 Mich.App. 293, 309-311, 833 N.W.2d 357 (2013), citing Carp, 298 Mich.App. at 522-532, 828 N.W.2d 685. Using this analysis, the trial court must then choose between imposing a sentence of life with or without parole. Eliason, 300 Mich.App. at 310, 833 N.W.2d 357. Eliason sought leave to appeal in this Court, challenging the sentencing procedures and options defined by the Court of Appeals, contending that the trial court should have the further option of imposing a sentence of a term of years. Eliason additionally argued that Const. 1963, art. 1, § 16 categorically bars the imposition of a life-without-parole sentence on a juvenile. We granted leave to appeal on both issues. People v. Eliason, 495 Mich. 891, 839 N.W.2d 193 (2013).
Pending our resolution of this appeal, and in response to Miller, the Legislature enacted, and the Governor signed into law, 2014 PA 22, now codified as MCL 769.25 and MCL 769.25a. This law significantly altered Michigan's sentencing scheme for juvenile offenders convicted of crimes that had previously carried a sentence of life without parole.
To understand the full context of defendants' appeals and the relief each seeks in reliance on Miller, it is necessary first to delineate the pre-Miller statutes that controlled the trial and sentencing of juvenile first-degree-murder offenders in Michigan. Each defendant before this Court was charged with first-degree murder under MCL 750.316. When a juvenile defendant "14 years of age or older" is charged with a felony, the family division of the circuit court would typically possess initial jurisdiction. MCL 712A.4(1). However, when a juvenile is charged with a "specified juvenile violation," including first-degree murder in violation of MCL 750.316, "the prosecuting attorney may authorize the filing of a complaint and warrant on the charge...." MCL 764.1f. If the prosecutor does so, the circuit court itself, rather than the family division of the circuit court, acquires jurisdiction over the juvenile defendant's case and must try that person as an adult. See MCL 712A.2(a)(1).
This process has been termed the "automatic waiver process" because the Legislature has vested exclusively in the prosecutor the executive discretion to charge and try a juvenile as an adult when the juvenile stands accused of first-degree murder. People v. Conat, 238 Mich.App. 134, 141-142, 605 N.W.2d 49 (1999). The prosecutors in the instant three cases filed complaints and warrants placing the cases within the jurisdiction of the circuit court, where each defendant was then tried and convicted as an adult. When this occurs and the offense is included in an enumerated
MCL 769.25, enacted in response to Miller, prescribes a new sentencing scheme for juveniles convicted of violating certain provisions of Michigan laws, such as MCL 750.316, that had previously carried with them a fixed sentence of life without parole. The effect of MCL 769.25 is that even juveniles who commit the most serious offenses against the laws of this state may no longer be sentenced under the same sentencing rules and procedures as those that apply to adults who commit the same offenses. Rather than imposing fixed sentences of life without parole on all defendants convicted of violating MCL 750.316, MCL 769.25 now establishes a default sentencing range for individuals who commit first-degree murder before turning 18 years of age. Pursuant to the new law, absent a motion by the prosecutor seeking a sentence of life without parole,
When, however, the prosecutor does file a motion seeking a life-without-parole sentence, the trial court "shall conduct a hearing on the motion as part of the sentencing process" and "shall consider the factors listed in Miller v. Alabama...." MCL 769.25(6). Accordingly, the sentencing of juvenile first-degree-murder offenders now provides for the so-called "individualized sentencing" procedures of Miller.
In adopting this new sentencing scheme, the Legislature was clearly cognizant of the issue surrounding whether Miller was to be applied retroactively. In defining the scope of the new scheme, the Legislature asserted that "the procedures set forth in [MCL 769.25] do not apply to any case that is final for purposes of appeal on or before June 24, 2012 [the day before the United States Supreme Court's decision in Miller]." MCL 769.25a(1). Instead, the Legislature specified:
Whether a decision of the United States Supreme Court applies retroactively under either federal or state retroactivity rules poses a question of law that is reviewed de novo. Maxson, 482 Mich. at 387, 759 N.W.2d 817. Whether a statute is constitutional also poses a question of law that is reviewed de novo. Hunter v. Hunter, 484 Mich. 247, 257, 771 N.W.2d 694 (2009). When the constitutionality of a statute is brought into question, "[t]he party challenging [it] has the burden of proving its invalidity." People v. Thomas, 201 Mich.App. 111, 117, 505 N.W.2d 873 (1993). To sustain its burden, the party challenging the statute must overcome the presumption that a statute is constitutional, and the statute "will not be declared unconstitutional unless clearly so, or so beyond a reasonable doubt." Cady v. Detroit, 289 Mich. 499, 505, 286 N.W. 805 (1939). Furthermore, a "party challenging the facial constitutionality of a statute faces an extremely rigorous standard, and must show that no set of circumstances exists under which the [a]ct would be valid." In re Request for Advisory Opinion Regarding Constitutionality of 2005 PA 71, 479 Mich. 1, 11, 740 N.W.2d 444 (2007) (citations and quotation marks omitted).
To determine whether Miller must be applied retroactively, it is helpful to first identify exactly what Miller held by way of understanding what precedents were relied on in forming its rule. Miller is the product of "two strands of precedent," one requiring a particular form of individualized sentencing before capital punishment can be imposed and the other addressing the constitutionality of imposing specific punishments on juvenile offenders. Miller, 567 U.S. at ___, 132 S.Ct. at 2463-2464. We now consider both strands of precedent with the purpose of identifying what is required by the rules formed from each strand of precedent and then comparing and contrasting what is required by each with what is required by the rule in Miller in order to determine whether the latter rule should be applied retroactively.
In Furman v. Georgia, 408 U.S. 238, 92 S.Ct. 2726, 33 L.Ed.2d 346 (1972), the United States Supreme Court decided 5-4 in seven separate opinions that it constituted cruel and unusual punishment in violation of the Eighth Amendment to impose capital punishment pursuant to a sentencing scheme that, in its words, "vested the [sentencer] with complete and unguided discretion to impose the death penalty...." Beck v. Alabama, 447 U.S. 625, 639, 100 S.Ct. 2382, 65 L.Ed.2d 392 (1980). In response, some states enacted sentencing schemes requiring the imposition of capital punishment for select crimes by way of the mandatory operation of law. Woodson v. North Carolina, 428 U.S. 280, 286-287, 298, 96 S.Ct. 2978, 49 L.Ed.2d 944 (1976). Those sentencing schemes were also challenged on Eighth Amendment grounds in Woodson, with the Court understanding the case as challenging not the state's ability to impose capital punishment but "the procedure employed by the State to select persons for the ... penalty of death." Id. at 287, 96 S.Ct. 2978 (emphasis added).
In Woodson, the Court, in another 5-4 decision, held that those schemes were unconstitutional. The plurality opinion
Following Woodson and Gregg, the United States Supreme Court confronted two additional cases challenging whether the sentencing procedures employed to impose capital punishment complied with Woodson's requirement of individualized sentencing determinations. See Lockett v. Ohio, 438 U.S. 586, 98 S.Ct. 2954, 57 L.Ed.2d 973 (1978), and Eddings v. Oklahoma, 455 U.S. 104, 102 S.Ct. 869, 71 L.Ed.2d 1 (1982). Both Lockett and Eddings were cited in Miller as part of the capital-punishment strand of precedent that culminated in Miller. Miller, 567 U.S. at ___, 132 S.Ct. at 2467. The plurality opinion in Lockett stated that statutory schemes authorizing capital punishment must permit the sentencer to consider all forms of mitigating evidence relating to two measuring points for determining the propriety of the sentence — evidence relating to the defendant's "character or record and any of the circumstances of the offense...." Lockett, 438 U.S. at 604, 98 S.Ct. 2954 (opinion by Burger, C.J.). Relevantly listed as factors that the sentencer must be permitted to consider were the defendant's "role in the offense" and the defendant's "age." Id. at 608, 98 S.Ct. 2954.
In Eddings, the Court, in a 5-4 decision, applied Lockett to a case in which the trial court, in considering mitigating factors before imposing capital punishment, declined to consider either the defendant's family background, including the physical abuse and neglect he had suffered, or the fact that he suffered from an alleged "personality disorder." Eddings, 455 U.S. at 112-113, 102 S.Ct. 869. The Court ruled that while a sentencer may "determine the weight to be given relevant mitigating evidence," the sentencer may not decide to give a piece of relevant mitigating evidence "no weight by [altogether] excluding such evidence from... consideration." Id. at 114-115, 102 S.Ct. 869. Under Lockett and Eddings, in which individualized sentencing is required, not only must statutory procedures for imposing capital punishment permit the defendant to present all relevant mitigating evidence, but the sentencer must also consider and accord some weight to that evidence. Id. at 112-115, 102 S.Ct. 869.
The second strand of precedent was developed in two cases, Roper v. Simmons, 543 U.S. 551, 125 S.Ct. 1183, 161 L.Ed.2d 1 (2005), and Graham. Roper and Graham, were understood by the Court in Miller to have "establish[ed] that children are constitutionally different from adults for purposes of sentencing." Miller, 567 U.S. at ___, 132 S.Ct. at 2464. This constitutional distinction has resulted in downward alterations in Roper and Graham in the range of punishments that the state may constitutionally impose on juvenile offenders. When the rules from Roper
In Roper, the Court held that the "Eighth and Fourteenth Amendments forbid imposition of the death penalty on offenders who were under the age of 18 when their crimes were committed." Roper, 543 U.S. at 578, 125 S.Ct. 1183. The Court characterized the rule it was adopting as a "categorical rule." Id. at 572, 125 S.Ct. 1183.
Miller v. Alabama created the rule that Carp and Davis seek to have applied retroactively. Having identified what is required by the rules from each of the two strands of precedent that underlie Miller, we now identify what is required by the rule in Miller in order to determine whether Miller is more like the juvenile-sentencing strand whose rules have applied retroactively under Teague or more like the capital-punishment strand whose rules have not been applied retroactively under Teague. We compare and contrast the rule in Miller in this way because, as discussed later, the "form and effect" of a rule is essential in determining whether a rule is to be applied retroactively under Teague. One form of a rule will produce a single invariable result, or a single effect, when applied to any defendant in the class of defendants to whom the rule is pertinent. Another form of a rule will produce a range of results, or have multiple possible effects, when applied to different defendants in the class of defendants to whom the rule is pertinent. The form and effect of the rules derived from the capital-punishment strand of precedent varies considerably from the form and effect of the rules derived from the juvenile-sentencing strand of precedent, and this variance has markedly different consequences for the question of retroactivity. The capital-punishment
Miller held "that the Eighth Amendment forbids a sentencing scheme that mandates life in prison without possibility of parole for juvenile offenders." Miller, 567 U.S. at ___, 132 S.Ct. at 2469. Within the very same paragraph in which Miller announced this holding, the Court also stated that its decision "require[s] [the sentencer] to take into account how children are different, and how those differences counsel against irrevocably sentencing them to a lifetime in prison." Id. at ___, 132 S.Ct. at 2469. Miller then provides substantial details regarding what must be considered as part of the individualized sentencing process before a sentence of life without parole can be imposed on a juvenile:
Miller's summarization of what the trial court must evaluate as part of the new individualized sentencing process tracks in large part the two measuring points about which a defendant must be allowed to present mitigating evidence within the capital-punishment context of Lockett — evidence relating to "the `circumstances of the particular offense and [to] the character and propensities of the offender.'" Id. at ___ n. 9, 132 S.Ct. at 2471 n. 9, quoting Roberts v. Louisiana, 428 U.S. 325, 333, 96 S.Ct. 3001, 49 L.Ed.2d 974 (1976) (opinion of Stewart, Powell, and Stevens, JJ.), and citing Sumner v. Shuman, 483 U.S. 66, 107 S.Ct. 2716, 97 L.Ed.2d 56 (1987). Although the focus of the rule in Miller — life-without-parole sentences for juvenile offenders — is, of course, distinct from the focus of the rules in capital-punishment cases, the form and effect of the rule in Miller is quite similar to that of the rules in capital-punishment cases. That is, the rule in Miller requires a sentencer to perform an individualized sentencing analysis resulting in a life-without-parole sentence being either imposed or not, very much like the capital-punishment cases
It is considerably more difficult to draw the same comparison between the rule in Miller and the categorical rules in Graham and Roper. Indeed, the United States Supreme Court itself specifically distinguished the form and effect of these rules:
Thus, rather than relying on Graham and Roper to give form and effect to Miller, in the same manner as the capital-punishment decisions, the Court relied on Graham and Roper in Miller only for a generalized "principle" regarding juvenile offenders. Id. at ___, 132 S.Ct. at 2471, 2472 n. 11. That is, Miller relied on Graham and Roper for the general principle of law that juveniles possess different mental faculties than adults, so the United States Constitution requires that they be treated differently than adults for sentencing purposes with respect to the imposition of capital punishment and sentences of life without parole. Although this principle of law explains why the United States Supreme Court found it necessary to adopt the rule in Miller, it has no bearing on the actual form and effect of the rule adopted in Miller. Accordingly, because the form
There is a "general rule of nonretroactivity for cases on collateral review" when it comes to applying new constitutional rules to cases that became final before the new rule was announced.
For this reason, the first inquiry in which a court must engage when
When a rule is deemed a "new rule" and the general rule of nonretroactivity applies, a court must then engage in Teague's second inquiry, to wit, whether the "new rule" satisfies one of Teague's two exceptions to the general rule of nonretroactivity for new rules. See id. If the "new rule" satisfies either of Teague's two exceptions, then it will be applied retroactively. Id. If, however, the "new rule" fails to satisfy either of those exceptions, the rule will only be entitled to prospective application. Id. Whorton succinctly summarized Teague's two exceptions to the general rule of nonretroactivity as follows:
Turning to the first inquiry of the retroactivity analysis, whether the rule in Miller is "new," we note that the United States Supreme Court has defined a rule as "new" when the rule "`breaks new ground,' `imposes a new obligation on the States or the Federal Government,' or was not `dictated by precedent existing at the time the defendant's conviction became final.'" Saffle, 494 U.S. at 488, 110 S.Ct. 1257, quoting Teague, 489 U.S. at 301, 109 S.Ct. 1060 (opinion by O'Connor, J.) (emphasis omitted). Essential to any of these bases for finding that a rule is "new" is the question of whether "all reasonable jurists would have deemed themselves compelled to accept" the rule at the time defendant's conviction became final. Graham v. Collins, 506 U.S. 461, 477, 113 S.Ct. 892, 122 L.Ed.2d 260 (1993) (emphasis added). The fact that a "decision is within the `logical compass' of an earlier decision ... is not conclusive for purposes of deciding whether the current decision is a `new rule' under Teague." Butler v. McKellar,
It is apparent, in our judgment, that the rule in Miller constitutes a new rule. Miller imposed a hitherto-absent obligation on state and lower federal courts to conduct individualized sentencing hearings before imposing a sentence of life without parole on a juvenile homicide offender. As part of this process, a prosecutor seeking a life-without-parole sentence must now present evidence of aggravating factors relevant to the offender and the offense, juvenile defendants must be afforded the opportunity and the financial resources to present evidence of mitigating factors relevant to the offender and the offense, psychological and other evaluations relevant to the youthfulness and maturity of the defendants must be allowed, and courts must now embark upon the consideration of aggravating and mitigating evidence offered regarding juvenile defendants as a condition to imposing sentences that previously required no such consideration. It thus seems certain as a result of Miller that a considerable number of juvenile defendants who would previously have been sentenced to life without parole for the commission of homicide offenses will have a lesser sentence meted out. Under Teague and Saffle, these new obligations clearly render the rule in Miller a new rule. We are not aware of any statement of this Court by any justice before Miller that argued in support of, or anticipated, the constitutional requirements set forth in that decision. Unless every affirmation by this Court of a sentence of life without parole on a juvenile offender before Miller, including those that followed decisions such as Roper, Graham, Eddings, and Lockett, can be characterized as "unreasonable," there cannot be serious argument that Miller did not define a "new rule."
Although Miller may be "within the logical compass" of earlier decisions, and built upon their foundation, cases predating Miller can hardly be read as having "dictated" or "compelled" Miller's result. Miller undoubtedly broke new ground in that it set forth the first constitutional rule to mandate individualized sentencing before noncapital punishment can be imposed. In this respect, the capital-punishment cases, although providing a model for the form and effect of Miller, would not have required a reasonable jurist to conclude that a life-without-parole sentence for a juvenile could only be constitutionally imposed following an individualized sentencing hearing.
Turning to the juvenile cases, Roper also dealt exclusively with the imposition of capital sentences without discussing the constitutionality of life-without-parole sentences and the need for individualized sentencing hearings. While Graham's focus was on life-without-parole sentences, its constitutional rule was limited to nonhomicide offenses, and it did not make individualized sentencing the constitutional threshold for imposing a sentence of life without parole. Furthermore, while Graham drew a comparison between life-without-parole sentences for juvenile offenders and capital punishment, which was pivotal in deciding Miller, Graham also stopped well short of finding the two punishments equivalent. See Graham, 560 U.S. at 69, 130 S.Ct. 2011. This is evident by Graham's reference to life without parole as "`the second most severe penalty permitted by law,'" id., quoting Harmelin v. Michigan, 501 U.S. 957, 1001, 111 S.Ct. 2680, 115 L.Ed.2d 836 (1991) (Kennedy, J.,
Concluding that Miller announced a new rule, we turn to the second inquiry, whether the rule in Miller fits within one of Teague's two "narrow exceptions" to the general rule of nonretroactivity. Saffle, 494 U.S. at 486, 110 S.Ct. 1257. At the outset, we note that neither Carp nor Davis advanced any argument before this Court suggesting that Miller should be applied retroactively under the second exception, the "watershed rule of criminal procedure" exception. Accordingly, we consider any argument regarding Miller identifying a "watershed rule of criminal procedure" unpreserved, and we will only consider whether the rule in Miller fits within the first exception to the general rule of nonretroactivity.
The first exception differentiates between new substantive rules and new procedural rules, allowing for the retroactive application of only the former. See Whorton, 549 U.S. at 417, 127 S.Ct. 1173; Schriro v. Summerlin, 542 U.S. 348, 351-352, 124 S.Ct. 2519, 159 L.Ed.2d 442 (2004). The origin of the first exception predates Teague, as that decision drew the contours of this exception from Justice Harlan's partial concurrence and partial dissent in Mackey v. United States, 401 U.S. 667, 91 S.Ct. 1160, 28 L.Ed.2d 404 (1971). Teague, 489 U.S. at 311, 109 S.Ct. 1060 (opinion by O'Connor, J.). In speaking of the "general" rule against retroactive application of new constitutional rules, Justice Harlan commented that the Court's
Justice Harlan supported this differentiation by emphasizing that retroactive application of a substantive rule "represents the clearest instance where finality interests should yield" because "[t]here is little societal interest in permitting the criminal process to rest at a point where it ought properly never to repose." Id. at 693, 109 S.Ct. 1060. Contrasting the retroactive application of a substantive rule with that of a procedural rule, Justice Harlan proceeded to offer the observation that the retroactive application of a substantive rule "entails none of the adverse collateral consequences of retrial" certain to follow the retroactive application of a procedural rule. Id. This is because a substantive rule precludes the possibility of retrial given that its application dictates a single result for the class of individuals or type of conduct formerly regulated by the old rule and now governed by the new rule. It is in this sense that categorical rules, such as those derived from the juvenile-sentencing strand of precedent, are substantive because they have a "form and effect" that always results in the imposed punishment being unconstitutional, i.e., they produce a "single result." Conversely, noncategorical rules, such as those derived from the capital-punishment strand of precedent — and Miller — are procedural because they have a "form and effect" that does not always result in the imposed punishment being unconstitutional, i.e., they do not produce a "single result." The latter rules merely require a court to perform a new or amended analysis before it can be determined whether a given punishment can be imposed on a particular defendant.
Teague subsequently adopted Justice Harlan's distinction between procedural and substantive rules, including the definition of when a rule is substantive. Teague, 489 U.S. at 310-311, 109 S.Ct. 1060 (opinion by O'Connor, J.). Since Teague, the United States Supreme Court has continued to recognize that the exceptions proposed by Justice Harlan in his opinion in Mackey were adopted in Teague. See, e.g., Danforth v. Minnesota, 552 U.S. 264, 273-275, 128 S.Ct. 1029, 169 L.Ed.2d 859 (2008); Penry, 492 U.S. at 329-330, 109 S.Ct. 2934; see also Schriro, 542 U.S. at 362, 124 S.Ct. 2519 (Breyer, J., dissenting).
Although Teague addressed whether a new rule germane to the trial stage of a criminal case could be applied retroactively, later cases have addressed whether new rules pertaining only to punishments and the sentencing phase are substantive and fit into Teague's first exception to the general rule of nonretroactivity. In so doing, the United States Supreme Court has provided three descriptions of what makes a new rule "substantive" within the context of a new rule governing the sentencing stage of a criminal case. Each of these, however, can be boiled down to whether the punishment imposed is one that the state has the authority to, and may constitutionally, impose on an individual within the pertinent class of defendants.
First, a new rule has been described as "substantive" when the rule "prohibit[s] a certain category of punishment for a class of defendants because of their status or offense." Penry, 492 U.S. at 330, 109 S.Ct. 2934; see also Saffle, 494 U.S. at 494-495, 110 S.Ct. 1257. Put another way, the new rule is "substantive" when the punishment at issue is categorically barred. The requirement that the new rule be "categorical" in its prohibition is
Second, a new rule has been described as "substantive" if it "alters the range of conduct or the class of persons that the law punishes." Schriro, 542 U.S. at 353, 124 S.Ct. 2519, citing Bousley v. United States, 523 U.S. 614, 620-621, 118 S.Ct. 1604, 140 L.Ed.2d 828 (1998). The dissent contends that when a new rule "expand[s] the range of punishments" available to the sentencer, the rule fits within this second description of a new rule as substantive. Post at 850. Although a new rule could potentially be viewed as altering the range of punishments available to the sentencer when the rule makes a previously unavailable lesser punishment available to the sentencer, the United States Supreme Court has adopted a different definition for when a new rule "alters the range" of available punishments. We are bound to abide by that definition when considering the rule in Miller for federal retroactivity purposes. Under that definition, a new rule alters the "range of conduct" that the law can punish when it "place[s] particular conduct or persons covered by the statute beyond the State's power to punish." Schriro, 542 U.S. at 352, 124 S.Ct. 2519 (emphasis added) (citations omitted). In this sense, the new rule transforms the conduct in which the defendant engaged, and which was previously within the state's power to regulate, into conduct that is no longer subject to criminal regulation. Applied in the context of rules governing sentencing and punishment, it must be the case that under the previous rule, the defendant "faces a punishment that the law cannot [any more] impose upon him" in light of the new rule. Id. In this sense, a new rule only "alters the range" of punishments available to the sentencer if it shifts the upper limits of the range of punishments downward so that the previously most severe punishment to which defendants have been sentenced is no longer a punishment that the sentencer may constitutionally impose.
Third, a new rule has been described as "substantive" when it "narrow[s] the scope of a criminal statute by interpreting its terms...." Id. at 351, 124 S.Ct. 2519, citing Bousley, 523 U.S. at 620-621, 118 S.Ct. 1604 (emphasis added). This third description addresses situations in which a criminal statute has previously been interpreted and applied beyond the statute's intended scope so that the "defendant stands convicted of `an act that the law does not make criminal.'" Bousley, 523 U.S. at 620, 118 S.Ct. 1604, quoting Davis v. United States, 417 U.S. 333, 346, 94 S.Ct. 2298, 41 L.Ed.2d 109 (1974).
In distinguishing what makes a new rule substantive, the United States Supreme Court has also afforded considerable direction regarding the qualities and contours of nonsubstantive, or procedural, rules. Simply put, "rules that regulate only the manner of determining the defendant's culpability are procedural." Schriro, 542 U.S. at 353, 124 S.Ct. 2519. This is because a rule that alters the "manner of determining" culpability "merely raise[s] the possibility that someone convicted with use of the invalidated procedure might have been acquitted otherwise." Id. at 352, 124 S.Ct. 2519. Applying this understanding to new rules governing sentences and punishments, a new procedural rule creates the possibility that the defendant would have received a less severe punishment but does not necessitate such a result. Accordingly, a rule is procedural when it affects how and under what framework a punishment may be imposed but leaves intact the state's fundamental legal authority to seek the imposition of the punishment on a defendant currently subject to the punishment.
Turning to how the United States Supreme Court has applied this distinction between substantive and procedural rules, in Schriro the Court was confronted with whether the new rule from Ring v. Arizona, 536 U.S. 584, 122 S.Ct. 2428, 153 L.Ed.2d 556 (2002), was substantive or procedural. Ring's rule invalidated Arizona's capital-punishment sentencing scheme and required that a jury rather than a judge make the determination whether aggravating factors necessary for the imposition of capital punishment had been proved. Id. at 609, 122 S.Ct. 2428. Despite the fact that Ring invalidated Arizona's statutory sentencing scheme authorizing capital punishment, its rule was ultimately deemed "procedural" on the basis that it
In Saffle, the Court similarly deemed a new rule "procedural" when it would have prohibited anti-sympathy instructions to juries performing the individualized sentencing process as a condition to imposing capital punishment. See Saffle, 494 U.S. at 486, 110 S.Ct. 1257. In doing so, Saffle stated that the rule "would neither decriminalize a class of conduct nor prohibit the imposition of capital punishment on a particular class of persons." Id. at 495, 110 S.Ct. 1257. It is with Schriro and Saffle in mind that we turn to the question of whether the rule in Miller is properly viewed as substantive or procedural.
Although the new procedures required by Miller may be more elaborate and detailed than the new procedures at issue in
Considering Miller's self-description of its rule, it is clear that the rule is not substantive within the terms of the first description of when a rule is substantive, i.e., when the rule "prohibit[s] a certain category of punishment for a class of defendants because of their status or offense." Penry, 492 U.S. at 330, 109 S.Ct. 2934; see also Saffle, 494 U.S. at 494, 110 S.Ct. 1257. The category of punishment implicated by Miller is a sentence of "life without parole,"
The second description of when a rule is substantive is equally of no avail to Carp and Davis because a rule is substantive under that description only when it alters the range of punishments that a state is permitted to impose by foreclosing the state's ability to impose the punishment defendant is serving. See Schriro, 542 U.S. at 353, 124 S.Ct. 2519. In this sense, a rule is only substantive if it acts to ratchet down the previously most severe punishment possible. Conversely, and contrary to the dissent, a rule will be considered procedural if it merely expands the range of possible punishments that may be imposed on the defendant. Applied to Michigan's sentencing scheme, Miller now requires the sentencer to consider imposing a sentence of life with the possibility of parole, but it does not require the sentencer to exclude from consideration a sentence of life without parole. Accordingly, Miller does not remove the punishment imposed on Carp and Davis from within the range of punishments the state has the power to impose. Accordingly, the rule in Miller again cannot be viewed as substantive under the second United States Supreme Court description.
The third description of when a rule is substantive is altogether inapplicable to Miller. The decision did not rest on any principle of statutory interpretation, and it did not pertain to a situation in which life-without-parole sentences were being imposed on juvenile homicide offenders absent
Ultimately, the rule in Miller is procedural because, as with the rule in Ring, it merely shifts "decisionmaking authority" for the imposition of a life-without-parole sentence on a juvenile homicide offender.
An additional consideration serves to strengthen this conclusion. In its description of the rule in Miller, the articulation employed by the United States Supreme Court is telling. Teague's retroactivity analysis distinguishing substantive and procedural rules is in no sense new or novel. Rather, the proposition that "substantive categorical guarantees" should receive retroactive application while "procedural noncategorical guarantees" should only receive prospective application predates Teague. See Penry, 492 U.S. at 329, 109 S.Ct. 2934. In the face of this reasonably well-defined and longstanding distinction, Miller, in describing the nature and scope of its rule, repeatedly employs language typically associated with nonretroactive procedural rules. Although fully recognizing that Roper and Graham announced "categorical" bars, Miller twice states that its rule does not create a "categorical" bar. Miller, 567 U.S. at ___, 132 S.Ct. at 2469, 2471. Furthermore, Miller, in straightforward terms, speaks of its rule as one that "mandates only that a sentencer follow a certain process[.]" Id. at ___, 132 S.Ct. at 2471 (emphasis added). It is hard to view these statements as anything other than expressions of continuity in the Court's understanding of the law of retroactivity, particularly in a circumstance in which the four justices of the Supreme Court who were presumably the least inclined to extend Miller to a broader range of cases — the dissenting justices who had rejected the new rule in the first place — were absent from the majority opinion.
Carp advances three arguments in an effort to overcome our conclusion that Miller does not qualify for retroactive application under Teague. First, he argues that each of the strands of precedent that underlie Miller has been granted retroactive status. While there may be considerable force to the argument that categorical rules like those in Roper and Graham must be applied retroactively under Teague, the same cannot be said for the strand of cases requiring individualized sentencing before capital punishment can be imposed on an adult offender. Despite considerable effort by Carp, including
In an effort to demonstrate to the contrary, Carp principally cites Sumner, in which the United States Supreme Court held that individualized sentencing was required before capital punishment could be imposed on a defendant, Shuman, who was serving a life-without-parole sentence at the time he committed the capital offense. Sumner, 483 U.S. at 80-81, 107 S.Ct. 2716. Carp is correct that Sumner relied on Woodson in creating its rule, id. at 70-75, 107 S.Ct. 2716, and is also correct that Sumner involved the review of a state conviction on collateral habeas review, see id. at 68, 107 S.Ct. 2716. However, not all cases presenting themselves on collateral review are equivalent for retroactivity purposes. Some cases on collateral review assert that state courts failed to properly apply constitutional rules in effect before the defendant's conviction became final, while others seek the application or creation of a new rule that was not announced before the defendant's conviction became final.
If, with respect to the application of Woodson, Sumner fell into the latter category, then we might agree with Carp that Woodson had been applied retroactively. Sumner, as it relates to the application of Woodson, however, falls into the former category of cases presenting themselves on collateral review. Woodson was decided on July 2, 1976, and Shuman's conviction did not become final for direct review purposes until May 17, 1978, nearly two years after Woodson was decided. See Shuman v. State, 94 Nev. 265, 578 P.2d 1183 (1978). Accordingly, to the extent that Woodson was applied in Sumner, it was simply not applied retroactively to a case that had become final for direct review purposes before Woodson was issued.
Apparently anticipating these flaws in the argument that Woodson has been applied retroactively, Carp contends that Sumner itself has been applied retroactively post-Teague. For this proposition, he cites Thigpen v. Thigpen, 926 F.2d 1003, 1005 (C.A.11, 1991). We, however, do not read Thigpen as addressing the question of Sumner's retroactivity. Although the district court below had applied Sumner retroactively to invalidate Thigpen's sentence, that portion of the district court's ruling was never appealed and the only issue before the United States Court of Appeals for the Eleventh Circuit was Thigpen's appeal concerning whether the
Accordingly, Carp has not succeeded in demonstrating that any of the individualized sentencing capital-punishment cases, i.e., Furman, Woodson, Lockett, Eddings, or Sumner, have been applied retroactively under Teague. This failure is pivotal given our earlier conclusion that the rule in Miller is of the same form and effect as the rules in the individualized sentencing capital-punishment cases.
Second, Carp argues that Miller has added "age" and "incorrigibility" as elements of what must be assessed before a life-without-parole sentence can be imposed on a juvenile offender. Carp argues that it follows from this that age and the juvenile offender's incorrigibility are aggravating factors that raise the mandatory minimum sentence that a defendant could receive under Michigan's pre-Miller sentencing scheme because they must now be shown by the state before a juvenile offender can be sentenced pursuant to MCL 750.316(1) and MCL 791.234(6). Citing Alleyne v. United States, 570 U.S. ___, 133 S.Ct. 2151, 2155, 186 L.Ed.2d 314 (2013), Carp notes that "any fact that increases the mandatory minimum is an `element' that must be submitted to the jury." Accordingly, he argues that the rule in Miller must be viewed as substantive and applied retroactively when it is considered in light of Alleyne because Miller combined with Alleyne substantively alters the way Michigan law defines and sentences juvenile homicide offenders.
Even assuming for the sake of argument that Miller made assessments of "age" and "incorrigibility" necessary elements for imposing a life-without-parole sentence on a juvenile homicide offender, Carp's argument still fails.
Third, Carp cites Miller's companion case of Jackson v. Hobbs as evidence that Miller has already been accorded retroactive status, and therefore presumably that the present judicial exercise has been rendered unnecessary. In offering this argument, Carp is correct that Jackson presented itself on collateral review and that the case was remanded for resentencing pursuant to the rule announced in Miller. Miller, 567 U.S. at ___, 132 S.Ct. at 2475. Accordingly, Carp also correctly notes that Jackson received retroactive relief under Miller. Id. at ___, 132 S.Ct. at 2475. That being said, the fact that Jackson received the benefit of Miller being applied retroactively does not lead to the conclusion that Miller must be applied retroactively to any other defendant. This is because the assertion that a rule is nonretroactive is an "affirmative defense," available to a prosecutor in objection to collateral relief being sought by a defendant. Thompson v. Runnels, 705 F.3d 1089, 1099 (C.A.9, 2013) (noting that Caspari v. Bohlen, 510 U.S. 383, 389, 114 S.Ct. 948, 127 L.Ed.2d 236 (1994) held that "`a federal court may, but need not, decline to apply Teague if the State does not argue it,' but `if the State does argue that the defendant seeks the benefit of a new rule of constitutional law, the court must apply Teague before considering the merits of the claim'"). As such, the nonretroactivity argument must be affirmatively raised by the state and when it is not raised, it is waived:
In this sense, a defense premised on the nonretroactivity of a new rule is "not `jurisdictional'" in nature, and the court does not have any duty sua sponte to conduct a retroactivity analysis. Collins v. Youngblood, 497 U.S. 37, 41, 110 S.Ct. 2715, 111 L.Ed.2d 30 (1990). Rather, because the question of retroactivity is "grounded in important considerations of federal-state relations," a state is free to "[choose] not to rely on Teague" without the federal courts' invalidating that choice. Id. By opting not to raise the defense in Jackson, the defense was waived and the question whether Miller should be applied retroactively was never presented to the United States Supreme Court.
As evidenced by the very quotation on which Carp relies, the application of the "principles of even-handed justice" only become relevant when the United States Supreme Court has actually undertaken a retroactivity analysis in the course of announcing a new rule. If no such analysis is necessary because of the posture of the case, as here, the Court will obviously not have the occasion to consider whether the new rule can be applied retroactively to all defendants who are situated similarly to the defendant before the Court.
Although states must apply a new rule of criminal procedure retroactively when the new rule satisfies Teague's exceptions to the general rule of nonretroactivity, they are permitted to "give broader retroactive effect" to a new rule than is required by Teague. Danforth, 552 U.S. at 288-289, 128 S.Ct. 1029. In this sense, Teague provides a floor for when a new rule of criminal procedure must be applied retroactively, with a state nonetheless free to adopt its own broader test for requiring the retroactive application of a new federal or state constitutional rule. See id. at 289-290, 109 S.Ct. 1060.
Michigan has adopted its own separate test for when a new rule of criminal procedure should be applied retroactively. See Maxson, 482 Mich. at 392-393, 759 N.W.2d 817. Michigan's test for retroactivity was originally derived from the pre-Teague federal test set forth in Linkletter v. Walker, 381 U.S. 618, 85 S.Ct. 1731, 14 L.Ed.2d 601 (1965). See People v. Hampton, 384 Mich. 669, 674, 187 N.W.2d 404 (1971).
Despite Michigan's having adopted its own retroactivity test that may give broader retroactive effect to some new rules than is mandated by the Teague test, Michigan nonetheless still adheres to the general principle of nonretroactivity for new rules of criminal procedure.
Michigan's test for retroactivity consists of three factors:
The first factor, the purpose factor, assesses the nature and focus of the new rule and the effect the rule is designed to have on the implementation of justice. See People v. Young, 410 Mich. 363, 366-367, 301 N.W.2d 803 (1981). Under this first factor, when a new rule "concerns the ascertainment of guilt or innocence, retroactive application may be appropriate." Id. at 367, 301 N.W.2d 803, citing Hampton, 384 Mich. 669, 187 N.W.2d 404 (emphasis added). Conversely, "[w]hen the ascertainment of guilt or innocence is not at stake, prospective application is possible" because "the purposes of the rule can be effectuated by prospective application." People v. Markham, 397 Mich. 530, 535, 245 N.W.2d 41 (1976). Consistent with this standard for when a rule should be applied only prospectively, "a new rule of procedure ... which does not affect the integrity of the fact-finding process should be given [only] prospective effect." Young, 410 Mich. at 367, 301 N.W.2d 803. Carp contends that Miller, although not implicating his guilt or innocence, nonetheless, goes to the "integrity of the fact-finding process" because it is essential to evaluating a defendant's level of culpability when imposing a sentence. In support of this contention, he cites McConnell v. Rhay, 393 U.S. 2, 3-4, 89 S.Ct. 32, 21 L.Ed.2d 2 (1968), in which pursuant to Linkletter, the United States Supreme Court retroactively applied a new rule of criminal procedure despite the new rule's being relevant only to the sentencing phase.
Two considerations, however, leave us unpersuaded that this remark necessitates the conclusion that the first factor of Michigan's test favors the retroactive application of Miller. First, the new rule applied retroactively in McConnell addressed the right to counsel, a right with unique significance both within the context of the criminal proceeding
Second, even if McConnell supported the expansive view that Carp attributes to it, that view is contrary to how Michigan law describes its own application of the Linkletter test. In every case to date in which this Court has applied the state retroactivity test, the "integrity of the fact-finding process" has always been referred to in the context of determining a defendant's "guilt or innocence." Maxson, 482 Mich. at 393-394, 759 N.W.2d 817; Sexton, 458 Mich. at 62, 580 N.W.2d 404; Young, 410 Mich. at 367, 301 N.W.2d 803. To the extent that McConnell may have viewed the "fact-finding process" as continuing throughout sentencing, we respectfully disagree and decline to adopt such an expansive view for purposes of our separate and independent test for retroactivity. It reflects an understanding of retroactivity that is no longer subscribed to by the United States Supreme Court and an understanding to which this Court has never subscribed. There is utterly no obligation on our part to forever maintain the Linkletter test in accordance with every past federal understanding when the test is now defunct for federal purposes and this Court, although initially relying on Linkletter to formulate our state test for retroactivity, has added its own interpretations to that test. Instead, the general principle of nonretroactivity for new rules of criminal procedure, to which Michigan adheres and which informs this state's retroactivity analysis, is properly served, in our judgment, by applying retroactively only those new rules of procedure that implicate the guilt or innocence of a defendant. We acknowledge that there are circumstances in which our state test may sometimes apply a new rule retroactively in circumstances in which Teague would not apply, but we are not prepared to extend our test beyond the federal test to the degree urged upon us by Carp.
In declining to expand the scope of the first factor of Michigan's state test for retroactivity, we note again that although our state test is derived from Linkletter,
From our holding that the first factor of our state test for retroactivity focuses on whether a new rule of procedure implicates a defendant's guilt or innocence, it is apparent that the first factor clearly militates against the retroactive application of Miller. As Miller alters only the process by which a court must determine a defendant's level of moral culpability for purposes of sentencing, it has no bearing on the defendant's legal culpability for the offense of which the defendant has been duly convicted.
In light then of our conclusion that the first state factor clearly counsels against the retroactive application of Miller, we find it relevant here to address the interplay between the three factors of the test and the weight that must be given to each before we determine the effect of the second and third factors on Miller's retroactive application. That a test consists of multiple factors does not logically signify that equal weight must be given to each. The United States Supreme Court, in applying the Linkletter test before it adopted the Teague test, observed that the second and third factors "have been regarded as having controlling significance `only when the purpose of the rule in question did not clearly favor either retroactivity or prospectivity.'" Michigan v. Payne, 412 U.S. 47, 55, 93 S.Ct. 1966, 36 L.Ed.2d 736 (1973), quoting Desist v. United States, 394 U.S. 244, 251, 89 S.Ct. 1030, 22 L.Ed.2d 248 (1969). Deductively from this statement, if two of the three factors only control when the first factor does not "clearly favor" retroactivity or prospectivity, it follows
Placing such an emphasis on the first factor is fully consistent with this Court's longstanding practice of dealing with the second and third factors "together." Young, 410 Mich. at 367, 301 N.W.2d 803; Hampton, 384 Mich. at 677, 187 N.W.2d 404. In this sense, the second and third factors will generally tend to produce a unified result that either favors or disfavors retroactivity. This is because the subject of the second factor (general reliance on the old rule) "will often have a profound effect on" the subject of the third factor (administration of justice), given that the greater the reliance by prosecutors of this state on a rule in pursuing justice, the more burdensome it will generally be for the judiciary to undo the administration of that rule. Sexton, 458 Mich. at 63-64, 580 N.W.2d 404; see also Hampton, 384 Mich. at 677-678, 187 N.W.2d 404. In light of the weight to be afforded the first factor when it clearly preponderates against retroactive application, our unified consideration of the second and third factors would need to favor retroactive application to a substantial degree in order for Miller to satisfy the requirements for retroactive application under our state test.
Turning to the inquiry required to evaluate the second and third factors "together," the second factor — the reliance on the old rule — must be considered both from the perspective of prosecutors across the state when prosecutors faithfully abided by the constitutional guarantees in place at the time of a defendant's conviction, see Adams v. Illinois, 405 U.S. 278, 283-284, 92 S.Ct. 916, 31 L.Ed.2d 202 (1972), and Johnson v. New Jersey, 384 U.S. 719, 731, 86 S.Ct. 1772, 16 L.Ed.2d 882 (1966), as well as from the collective perspective of the 334 defendants who would be entitled to resentencing if the new rule were applied retroactively, see Maxson, 482 Mich. at 394, 759 N.W.2d 817. Inherent in the question of reliance by prosecutors across the state is the extent to which the old rule received constitutional approval from the judiciary before the adoption of the new rule. See Tehan v. United States ex rel. Shott, 382 U.S. 406, 417, 86 S.Ct. 459, 15 L.Ed.2d 453 (1966). When the old rule is merely the result of a "negative implication" drawn by prosecutors, the prosecutors' good-faith reliance on the old rule is at its most minimal. Brown v. Louisiana, 447 U.S. 323, 335, 100 S.Ct. 2214, 65 L.Ed.2d 159 (1980) (opinion by Brennan, J.). Similarly, when the old rule was of "doubtful constitutionality," the ability of prosecutors across the state to rely on the old rule in good faith is diminished. Id. Conversely, when the old rule has been specifically approved by the courts as passing constitutional muster, prosecutors have their strongest argument for having relied on the old rule in good faith. Tehan, 382 U.S. at 417, 86 S.Ct. 459. Moreover, when prosecutors relied in good faith on the old rule and did so for a lengthier period of time, reliance can be viewed as more significant and the second factor will tend to counsel against retroactive application. Id. As for defendants' reliance on the old rule, they must demonstrate not only that they relied on the old rule by taking or not taking a specific action, but that they "detrimentally relied on the old rule." Maxson, 482 Mich. at 394, 759 N.W.2d 817 (emphasis added).
Applying these considerations in evaluating the second and third factors to Miller, it is apparent that these factors do not sufficiently favor the retroactive application of Miller so as to overcome the first factor's clear direction against its retroactive application. The old rule permitting life-without-parole sentences on the basis of the pre-Miller sentencing scheme established by the Legislature received in 1996 the specific approval of its constitutionality by our judiciary. Launsburry, 217 Mich. App. at 363-365, 551 N.W.2d 460. Further, nothing in United States Supreme Court caselaw called into any question life-without-parole sentences for any juvenile offenders until Graham was decided in 2010, and even then Graham was specifically limited in its breadth to juveniles who committed nonhomicide offenses.
On the basis of this state of the law, prosecutors across Michigan entirely in
Conversely, we note that this is not a situation in which it can fairly be said that, as a group, the 334 defendants who would be entitled to resentencing if the rule in Miller were applied retroactively have "relied" on the old rule to their "detriment." First, we find it difficult to understand, and Carp and Davis themselves fail to identify, exactly what adverse action the 334 defendants have taken, or opted not to take, in "reliance" on the old rule (except perhaps to recognize and abide by the old rule as the then extant law of this state).
Second, even to the extent that any defendants can be said to have taken or foregone some action to their detriment in reliance on the old rule, they still can only be said to have "detrimentally" relied on the old rule if they can establish that they would have obtained a result more favorable to them under the new rule. Maxson, 482 Mich. at 394-396, 759 N.W.2d 817. In this sense, defendants can only be said to have "`detrimentally relied' on the old rule" if they "suffered actual harm from [their] reliance...." Id. at 396, 759 N.W.2d 817. However, a majority of the 334 defendants who would receive resentencing hearings if the rule in Miller were applied retroactively were between 17 and 18 years of age when they committed their homicide offenses. Because Miller requires a sentencing court to give specific consideration to the age and the mental development of a juvenile offender before imposing a sentence of life without parole, when a juvenile most closely approaches the age of majority at the time the juvenile commits a homicide offense, Miller would seem least likely to counsel in favor of sentencing that juvenile with special leniency, given that in only as few as several months the juvenile would be ineligible for any leniency at all.
As between defendants and the prosecutors of this state, it is further apparent that the latter have relied far more heavily on the old rule, have done so in good faith, and would have relied "detrimentally" on
Miller requires trial courts to determine a defendant's moral culpability for the murder the defendant has committed by examining the defendant's character and mental development at the time of the offense. Even if the myriad evidence could somehow be obtained by the prosecutor, it is fanciful to believe that the backward-looking determination then required of the trial court could be undertaken with sufficient accuracy and trustworthiness so many years after the crime had been committed, the trial completed, and the defendant sentenced. Further, just as the prosecutor might no longer be available to represent the people's interest, neither might the sentencing judge. We are not confident that the justice achieved by a resentencing process taking place many years after the original trial and sentencing — many years after the victims of the homicide have become little more than historical footnotes to all but their immediate families — and presided over by a judge who can never entirely be situated like the judge who presided over the trial, can effectively replicate the justice achieved at the initial sentencing. Instead, we believe that the trial court's ability to travel back in time to assess a defendant's mental state of some 20 years earlier — evidence of which may not even have been gathered at the time — is limited; that the recollection of memories about aggravating and mitigating circumstances — evidence of which may again not even have been gathered at the time — is questionable; and that, as a result, public confidence in the integrity and accuracy of those proceedings will understandably be low.
For these reasons, we find that the second and third factors do not sufficiently favor the retroactive application of Miller
Defendants raise a series of constitutional challenges arguing that the Eighth Amendment of the United States Constitution or Const. 1963, art. 1, § 16, or both, categorically bars the imposition of a life-without-parole sentence on a juvenile homicide offender. We consider each challenge in turn.
Defendants assert that the Eighth Amendment of the United States Constitution
As noted earlier, the holding in Roper was specifically limited to capital punishment in that the "Eighth and Fourteenth Amendments forbid imposition of the death penalty on offenders who were under the age of 18 when their crimes were committed." Roper, 543 U.S. at 578, 125 S.Ct. 1183. Given that capital punishment was only "likened" to life without parole for a juvenile offender, Miller, 567 U.S. at ___, 132 S.Ct. at 2463-2464, rather than deemed equivalent to life without parole for a juvenile offender, neither Roper nor Roper in conjunction with Graham and Miller suggests in any way that the Eighth Amendment must be read as invalidating the state's ability to impose a life-without-parole sentence on a juvenile homicide offender. Likewise, Graham's holding was specifically limited so as to categorically bar only the imposition of life-without-parole sentences for juvenile offenders convicted of nonhomicide offenses. Graham, 560 U.S. at 79, 130 S.Ct. 2011. Accordingly, Graham also does not compel the invalidation of a state's ability to impose a sentence of life without parole on a juvenile homicide offender.
Turning lastly to Miller, its rule is specifically limited in that it counsels against the very categorical rule sought by defendants. As discussed earlier, Miller requires that an individualized sentencing hearing occur before a life-without-parole
Defendants alternatively contend that, in light of the manner in which state legislatures reacted to Miller by adjusting sentencing schemes governing juvenile homicide offenders, it is now, pursuant to the proportionality review employed in Roper, Graham, and Miller, cruel and unusual punishment to impose a life-without-parole sentence on a juvenile homicide offender. Within the context of the Eighth Amendment, the United States Supreme Court has used a multipart test to determine if a punishment imposed on a juvenile offender is disproportionate:
Starting with the preliminary question whether "the gravity of the offense" is commensurate with "the severity of the sentence," Graham, 560 U.S. at 60, 130 S.Ct. 2011, we note that first-degree murder is almost certainly the gravest and most serious offense that an individual can commit under the laws of Michigan — the premeditated taking of an innocent human life. It is, therefore, unsurprising that the people of this state, through the Legislature, would have chosen to impose the most severe punishment authorized by the laws of Michigan for this offense. Although the individualized sentencing process now required by Miller (and as a necessary response to Miller by MCL 769.25) may perhaps indicate that some juvenile offenders lack the moral culpability and mental faculties to warrant a life-without-parole sentence pursuant to the premises of Miller, when the contrary conclusions are drawn, as they presumably will be in some cases, a sentence of life without parole for first-degree murder will not "lead[] to an inference of gross disproportionality." Id. Accordingly, defendants have failed to demonstrate that the imposition of a life-without-parole sentence will satisfy the first part of the United States Supreme Court's test for proportionality. As the first part of this federal test is a necessary requirement for finding that a punishment is "disproportionate," defendants' facial challenge fails as they are consequently unable to demonstrate that the Eighth Amendment categorically bars the imposition of a life-without-parole sentence on juvenile homicide offenders.
Even if defendants had satisfied the first part of the federal test for disproportionality, however, they have also failed to satisfy the second part of the test, which compares the life-without-parole sentence defendants seek to invalidate "with the sentences received by other offenders in the same jurisdiction and with the sentences imposed for the same
First, as noted in the first part of this test for proportionality, first-degree murder is almost certainly the gravest and most serious offense that can be committed under the laws of Michigan. As with juveniles, adult offenders who commit the offense of first-degree murder face the same sentence of life without parole. Because some juvenile offenders will possess the same mental faculties of an adult so that they are equally able to recognize the consequences of their crimes and form an unequivocal premeditated intent to kill in the face of the consequences, it is not categorically disproportionate to punish at least some juvenile offenders the same as adults.
Second, there are some nonhomicide offenses that may be viewed as less grave and less serious than first-degree murder and for which only adult offenders face a life-without-parole sentence in this state. For instance, an adult who commits successive first-degree criminal sexual conduct offenses against an individual under the age of 13 faces a sentence of life without parole. MCL 750.520b(2)(c). Accordingly, when the commission of a nonhomicide offense by an adult offender may result in the imposition of a life-without-parole sentence, it does not appear categorically disproportionate to impose a life-without-parole sentence on a juvenile offender for committing the gravest and most serious homicide offense.
Third, although this Court is required by Graham to assess the proportionality of a sentence of life without parole imposed on juveniles who commit first-degree murder, we would be derelict if we did not observe that the people of this state, acting through their Legislature, have already exercised their judgment — to which we owe considerable deference — that the sanction they have selected for juvenile first-degree-murder offenders is, in fact, a proportionate sanction. We are not certain that there is a superior test for assessing a determination of proportionality than that a particular sanction is compatible with public opinion and sentiment. Nonetheless, because this Court is required to do so by Graham, we undertake to the best of our ability to exercise independent judgment in analyzing the criminal punishments authorized by our Legislature and assessing their propriety in the light of the crimes for which the Legislature has deemed them proportionate.
Turning to whether Michigan's sentencing scheme for juvenile first-degree-murder offenders is "disproportionate" to sentencing schemes used in other states, defendants have wholly failed to present relevant data demonstrating that Michigan is an outlier when it comes to permitting the imposition of life-without-parole sentences for juvenile first-degree-murder offenders, even on the assumption that being an "outlier" adversely affects our state's compliance with the United States Constitution. Defendants in their briefs cherry-pick six states in which sentencing schemes have been altered post-Miller to eliminate life-without-parole as a possible sentence for juvenile offenders. The fact that six states have eliminated life-without-parole sentences for juvenile offenders in response to Miller tells us next to nothing about how Michigan's choice to impose life-without-parole sentences on juveniles convicted of first-degree murder compares to
What trend is demonstrated by the actions of these six states alone? How many states at the time of Miller imposed a sentence of life without parole on juvenile homicide offenders? How many of these states responded to Miller in a manner similar to that of Michigan? What is apparent is that at the time of Miller, "26 States ... [made] life without parole the mandatory (or mandatory minimum) punishment for some form of murder, and would apply the relevant provision to 14-year-olds...." Miller, 567 U.S. at ___ n. 9, 132 S.Ct. at 2471 n. 9. Another 15 states allowed for the discretionary imposition of life-without-parole sentences on juvenile offenders. Id. at ___ n. 10, 132 S.Ct. at 2472 n. 10. Combined therefore, 41 states exercised the authority under at least some circumstances to impose a life-without-parole sentence on a juvenile. If, as defendants assert, six of those states have departed from this practice by eliminating that sentence altogether, can it be concluded that life-without-parole sentences for juveniles are disproportionate when they remain an option of some kind in 35 states in total, or 70% of the states composing the Union?
In summary, we have no evidence that sustains defendants' burden of demonstrating that Michigan's statutory scheme is categorically disproportionate to those of other states. As defendants have failed to demonstrate that either part of the federal test for the constitutionality of punishments supports the conclusion that a life-without-parole sentence for juvenile homicide offenders is disproportionate, we decline to hold that the Eighth Amendment of the United States Constitution categorically bars that punishment.
Defendants next contend that even if the Eighth Amendment does not categorically bar the imposition of sentences of life without parole on juvenile homicide offenders, Const. 1963, art. 1, § 16 does mandate such a categorical bar. Whereas the Eighth Amendment proscribes the imposition of "cruel and unusual punishments," Const. 1963, art. 1, § 16 states:
The textual difference between the federal constitutional protection and the state constitutional protection is of consequence and has led this Court to conclude that Article 1, § 16 provides greater protection against certain punishments than its federal counterpart in that if a punishment must be both "cruel" and "unusual" for it to be proscribed by the Eighth Amendment, a "punishment that is unusual but not necessarily cruel" is also proscribed by Article 1, § 16. People v. Lorentzen, 387 Mich. 167, 172, 194 N.W.2d 827 (1972).
This broader protection under Article 1, § 16 against punishments that are merely "unusual" has led this Court to adopt a slightly different and broader test for proportionality than that employed in Graham. See id. at 171-172, 194 N.W.2d 827; see also People v. Bullock, 440 Mich. 15, 31, 485 N.W.2d 866 (1992).
At the outset, we note that the Lorentzen/Bullock test bears a considerable resemblance to the federal test for proportionality because the first three factors combine to effect the same general inquiry as the two-part test employed in Graham, See Bullock, 440 Mich. at 33, 485 N.W.2d 866 ("Our analysis in Lorentzen foreshadowed in a striking manner the three-pronged test later adopted by the United States Supreme Court in Solem v. Helm, 463 U.S. 277, 290-291, 103 S.Ct. 3001, 77 L.Ed.2d 637 (1983)."). Our conclusion that none of the first three factors supports the inference that a life-without-parole sentence for a juvenile offender is disproportionate under the Eighth Amendment also bears on the first three inquires of the proportionality analysis under the Lorentzen/Bullock test. Accordingly, only the fourth factor of the Lorentzen/Bullock test remains to be assessed before weighing these factors and reaching a conclusion about the proportionality of a life-without-parole sentence for a juvenile homicide offender under Article 1, § 16 of our state constitution.
Concerning the fourth factor, we concur with the United States Supreme Court's assessment that a life-without-parole sentence for a juvenile does not serve the penological goal of rehabilitation.
Davis argues that even if the Eighth Amendment does not categorically bar imposing sentences of life without parole on juvenile homicide offenders, it at least categorically bars imposing life-without-parole sentences on juvenile homicide offenders, such as himself, convicted of felony murder ostensibly on the basis of an aiding-and-abetting theory. At the outset of our analysis, we note that our Legislature has chosen to treat offenders who aid and abet the commission of an offense in exactly the same manner as those offenders who more directly commit the offense:
Moreover, the Legislature has enacted a felony-murder statute, which treats the commission of a murder during the course of a robbery as first-degree murder. See MCL 750.316(1)(b).
Davis attempts to overcome this constitutional pronouncement in light of his own proposed categorical rule mandating a lesser maximum penalty for aiders and abettors by asserting that Miller and Graham combine to necessitate such a rule. He advances a two-part argument to this effect: (1) the rule in Miller requires individualized sentencing for juvenile offenders in an effort to account for "their lesser culpability," Miller, 567 U.S. at ___, 132 S.Ct. at 2463, and (2) Graham, has already determined that aiders and abettors are sufficiently less culpable that a sentence of life without parole is never constitutionally appropriate, see Graham, 560 U.S. at 69, 130 S.Ct. 2011.
Although the first part of this syllogism is undoubtedly accurate, the same cannot be said of the second part. Graham made two statements pertinent to the second part of Davis's argument:
In combination with Miller's requirement that individualized sentencing account for a juvenile's "lesser culpability," it has been argued that a juvenile offender cannot be sentenced to life without parole when the defendant did not kill, intend to kill, or foresee that life would be taken as a result of the offense, even when the offense of which the offender was convicted was felony murder. Just such a contention was advanced by Justice Breyer in his concurrence in Miller, in which, addressing specifically the constitutionality of life-without-parole sentences for juvenile offenders convicted of felony murder on an aiding-and-abetting theory, he stated, "Graham dictates a clear rule: The only juveniles who may constitutionally be sentenced to life without parole are those convicted of homicide offenses who `kill or intend to kill.'" Miller, 567 U.S. at ___, 132 S.Ct. at 2476 (Breyer, J., concurring).
Assuming for the sake of argument that some categorical rule of this nature is the necessary product of Graham and Miller,
This conclusion is entirely consistent with, and arguably dictated by, the individualized
Eliason asserts that Const. 1963, art. 1, § 16 categorically bars the imposition of a sentence of life without parole on a juvenile homicide offender who is 14 years of age at the time of the offense. For Eliason's facial challenge to be ripe, there must be "a real and immediate threat ... as opposed to a hypothetical one" that a sentence of life without parole will be imposed on him. Conat, 238 Mich. App. at 145, 605 N.W.2d 49, citing Los Angeles v. Lyons, 461 U.S. 95, 101-101, 103 S.Ct. 1660, 75 L.Ed.2d 675 (1983), and Dep't of Social Servs. v. Emmanuel Baptist Preschool, 434 Mich. 380, 410, 455 N.W.2d 1 (1990) (CAVANAGH, J.). Put differently, in determining whether an issue is justiciably "ripe," a court must assess "`whether the harm asserted has matured sufficiently to warrant judicial intervention.'" Emmanuel Baptist, 434 Mich. at 412 n. 48, 455 N.W.2d 1 (citation omitted).
Eliason was 14 years of age at the time of his offense and was initially sentenced to life without parole. However, because Eliason's case is on direct review, he is entitled to resentencing pursuant to MCL 769.25(1)(b)(ii). Under MCL 769.25(9), the default sentence for a juvenile convicted of first-degree murder is a sentence of a term of years within specific limits rather than life without parole. A juvenile defendant will only face a life-without-parole sentence if the prosecutor files a motion seeking that sentence and the trial court concludes following an individualized sentencing hearing in accordance with Miller that such a sentence is appropriate. MCL 769.25(2) through (7).
Although the prosecutor has filed a motion seeking the imposition of a sentence of life without parole, it is no more than speculation whether the trial court will depart from the default sentence in response to the prosecutor's motion and impose a life-without-parole sentence, and it is not apparent that Eliason faces a "real and immediate" threat of receiving a life-without-parole sentence. Furthermore, because he will be facing a minimum sentence of "not less than 25 years," MCL 769.25(9), to deny on ripeness grounds the relief Eliason seeks will cause him no legally cognizable hardship or harm. If a life-without-parole sentence is imposed at resentencing, Eliason will have more than ample time to appeal and assert either an as-applied or a facial constitutional challenge to his sentence before he completes the minimum possible sentence for his offense. Accordingly, in light of Eliason's being entitled to resentencing under MCL 769.25, his facial constitutional challenge to life-without-parole sentences for juvenile homicide offenders who are 14 years of age at the time of their offense is no longer justiciable.
For these reasons, we hold that the rule set forth in Miller should not be retroactively applied under either the federal retroactivity test set forth in Teague or Michigan's separate and independent retroactivity test set forth in Sexton and Maxson. In so doing, we affirm the judgments of the Court of Appeals in Carp and Davis that Miller should not be applied retroactively. We further hold that neither the Eighth Amendment nor Const. 1963, art. 1, § 16 categorically bars the imposition of a sentence of life without parole on a juvenile first-degree-murder offender or a juvenile convicted of felony murder on the basis of an aiding-and-abetting theory. Finally, we hold that Eliason's facial constitutional challenge is no longer ripe and therefore remand his case for resentencing pursuant to MCL 769.25.
YOUNG, C.J., ZAHRA, and VIVIANO, JJ., concurred with MARKMAN, J.
KELLY, J. (dissenting).
In a series of recent cases involving juvenile offenders,
The Eighth Amendment of the United States Constitution prohibits the infliction of "cruel and unusual punishments"
"`The basic concept underlying the Eighth Amendment is nothing less than the dignity of man.'"
In these rulings, the Court relied on three significant differences between juveniles and adults to conclude that juveniles have "diminished culpability" for their crimes and "greater prospects for reform."
These differences between juveniles and adults "diminish the penological justifications for imposing the harshest sentences on juvenile offenders, even when they commit
Not only is age relevant in establishing an offender's culpability for the crime, as already explained in this opinion, but it is also relevant in determining whether punishment for a crime is sufficiently comparable in severity to an identical sentence given to an adult offender. Sentencing a juvenile offender to a nonparolable life sentence is "`especially harsh'" given that the offender "will almost inevitably serve `more years and a greater percentage of his life in prison than an adult offender.'"
In particular, the Supreme Court questioned the ability of mandatory penalties to take into account the unique circumstances of youth: "mandatory penalties, by their nature, preclude a sentencer from taking account of an offender's age and the wealth of characteristics and circumstances attendant to it."
The Supreme Court invalidated any "sentencing scheme that mandates life in prison without possibility of parole for juvenile offenders."
It is undisputed — and cannot be disputed — that Miller applies to all cases that were pending on direct appeal when the decision was issued on June 25, 2012, and that it applies to all juvenile offenders going forward.
In Teague v. Lane and its progeny, the United States Supreme Court has explained when its new rules are retroactive under federal law and thereby apply to cases on collateral review.
Once the reviewing court determines that the Supreme Court issued a new rule of law in the case being analyzed, the reviewing court must then determine whether the new rule is a substantive rule or a procedural rule:
A rule is procedural if it "regulate[s] only the manner of determining the defendant's culpability" or if it "allocate[s] decisionmaking authority."
It is uncontested that Miller is a new rule, and we agree with the majority's conclusion that "Miller imposed a hitherto-absent obligation on state and lower federal courts to conduct individualized sentencing hearings before imposing a sentence of life without parole on a juvenile homicide offender."
We disagree, however, with the majority's conclusion that Miller is best characterized as a procedural ruling such that it applies retroactively to cases on collateral review only if it is a watershed rule of constitutional procedure. Admittedly, the distinction between rules of procedure and rules of substance "is not necessarily always a simple matter to divine."
State legislatures have the "substantive power to define crimes and prescribe punishments,"
After Miller, if a state chooses to permit the sentencing of juveniles to nonparolable life,
The majority claims that the distinction between the "categorical bar" of a penalty and the "noncategorical bar" of a penalty "defines the critical element of the retroactivity analysis in Teague."
The substantive nature of Miller's holding becomes clearer upon considering that it did not invalidate mandatory sentencing schemes as applied to adult offenders.
After Miller, the offender's age at the time of the offense determines which of two sentencing schemes applies to the offender — that is, whether the offender is subject to a mandatory nonparolable life sentence (because the offender is an adult) or whether the sentence must take into account the offender's age and characteristics of youth, as well as the circumstances of the offense (because the offender is a juvenile).
The majority analyzes what it deems the "form and effect" of Miller and concludes differently. Under its rationale, Miller is not retroactive in large part because the Supreme Court did not categorically bar a sentence as applied to a class of individuals, which it did in Roper and Graham. Rather, juvenile offenders sentenced to nonparolable life have been given a punishment that is within the power of the state to impose. The majority thus determines that Miller is more similar to cases involving the individualized imposition of the death penalty, which, the majority asserts, are cases involving new procedural rules.
The majority is insightful, to a point, by comparing Miller with Woodson v. North Carolina, which struck down a sentencing scheme that mandated the death penalty upon conviction of certain offenses.
While Woodson required a state to provide some sort of procedural mechanism before it could impose capital punishment, it only offered minimal guidance on what procedures are required and, specifically, on who should decide whether an individual was eligible to receive the death penalty. After Woodson, some states listed aggravating factors that rendered an offense eligible for the death penalty. The Supreme Court subsequently held, in Ring v. Arizona, that the Sixth Amendment right to a jury trial requires a jury to determine the presence or absence of the aggravating factors that qualify an offender as death-eligible.
In Schriro v. Summerlin, the Supreme Court determined that Ring was procedural, and therefore not retroactive, because the aggravating factors at issue there remained "subject to the procedural requirements the Constitution attaches to trial of elements."
The majority glosses over the substantive import of this distinction, and in doing so ignores the fact that, both before and after Ring, there existed the possibility for a punishment less than death, while only after Miller does there exist the possibility
Indeed, if Miller were merely a procedural decision, the Supreme Court would not have examined — and found wanting — the penological aims of a state legislature's substantive policy choice to impose a mandatory nonparolable life sentence on juvenile homicide offenders. In fact, in Miller, the Court explained that none of the permissible penological aims — retribution, deterrence, incapacitation, and rehabilitation — warrant mandatory nonparolable sentences for juvenile offenders.
Nevertheless, Atkins acknowledged that states are provided with considerable discretion to fashion procedures to determine whether an offender must be excluded from consideration of the death penalty:
Miller likewise provided states with considerable discretion to determine how a juvenile offender is to be adjudged sufficiently culpable as an individual to warrant imposition of a nonparolable life sentence.
In the end, the majority strains to place Miller in a procedural box into which it will not comfortably fit. Miller is based on the substantive differences between juveniles and adults and the potentially reduced culpability of juveniles for the crimes that they commit. While there are procedural implications to the decision — as Miller itself acknowledged — the "form and effect" of the opinion, to use the majority's phrase, is that the Eighth Amendment places a substantive limitation on how states can punish juvenile offenders. Accordingly, we would hold that Miller applies retroactively under federal law.
Even if we were to agree with the majority that Miller announced a new rule of criminal procedure, which we do not, an alternative basis supports our conclusion that Miller should apply retroactively. That is, as a separate and independent matter, we would hold that Miller applies retroactively under state law. It is to that analysis that we now turn.
This Court has consistently asserted that three factors are relevant in determining whether a new rule of criminal procedure should be applied retroactively under state law, even if such a new rule of criminal procedure does not apply retroactively under federal law:
The county prosecutors involved in these cases and the Attorney General argue that this Court should reverse this existing caselaw and rule that the retroactivity analysis under Michigan law is identical to the retroactivity analysis under federal law as articulated in Teague and its progeny. They claim that our caselaw is outdated because it applies the test for retroactivity that the Supreme Court abandoned in Teague.
As stated, the first factor that a reviewing court must consider in assessing a new rule's retroactivity under state law is the purpose of the new rule. "Under the `purpose' prong, a law may be applied retroactively when it `concerns the ascertainment of guilt or innocence[,]' however, `a new rule of procedure ... which does not affect the integrity of the fact-finding process should be given prospective effect.'"
The second factor "examines whether individual persons or entities have been `adversely positioned ... in reliance' on the old rule."
Indeed, applying the third factor takes into account this reliance on the old rule by examining whether applying the new rule retroactively would undermine the state's "strong interest in finality of the criminal justice process...."
The majority concludes that requiring a sentencing hearing for offenders whose direct appeals are complete would be "burdensome and complicated," if not "almost impossibl[e]...."
Because each of these factors supports retroactive application of Miller under state law, we would hold that independent state law grounds exist to apply Miller retroactively.
For the reasons stated in this opinion, we respectfully dissent from the majority's decision not to apply Miller v. Alabama retroactively under either federal or state law. Instead, we would reverse the Court of Appeals in Carp and Davis and remand to the St. Clair Circuit Court and Wayne Circuit Court, respectively, for resentencing pursuant to MCL 769.25a.
MICHAEL F. CAVANAGH and McCORMACK, JJ., concurred with MARY BETH KELLY, J.
Of the 334 affected defendants, 4 were 14 years of age when they committed their first-degree-murder offenses, 44 were 15 years of age, 105 were 16 years of age, and 181 were 17 years of age. Of the 181 defendants who were 17 years of age at the time of their offenses, 28 were within two months of turning 18 years of age, with several of those individuals within days of turning 18. As for when the defendants were initially sentenced, 172 of the defendants were sentenced at least 20 years ago, with several sentenced as early as the mid-to late 1970s. Another 83 defendants were sentenced between 15 and 20 years ago, 46 were sentenced between 10 and 15 years ago, 33 were sentenced between 5 and 10 years ago, and none were sentenced within the last 5 years.
In applying this standard, the only rule that the United States Supreme Court has ever identified as a "watershed rule" for purpose of Teague's second exception is the rule drawn from Gideon v. Wainwright, 372 U.S. 335, 83 S.Ct. 792, 9 L.Ed.2d 799 (1963), which established that the Sixth Amendment included the right to appointed counsel at trial for indigent defendants. See Whorton, 549 U.S. at 419, 127 S.Ct. 1173. Furthermore, the sentencing rule in Miller has no possible effect in preventing any "impermissibly large risk of an inaccurate conviction" and pertains to no "bedrock procedural elements essential to the fairness of a proceeding."
Contrary to the majority's claim, it is irrelevant that the Supreme Court has abandoned the pre-Teague framework in determining the application of this state's independent retroactivity jurisprudence. Indeed, saying that this Court has "no obligation ... to forever maintain the Linkletter test in accordance with every past federal understanding," ante at 834, classifying the foundational caselaw of Michigan's retroactivity test as "defunct," ante at 834, and stating that "only the extraordinary new rule of criminal procedure," whatever that may mean, "will be applied retroactively under Michigan's test when retroactivity is not already mandated under Teague," ante at 833 comes perilously close to deciding to maintain the principles underlying this state's traditional retroactivity framework only when Teague and its progeny militate in favor of retroactivity. We would not turn Michigan's retroactivity framework into such a parchment barrier. See Federalist No. 48 (James Madison) (Wright ed., 2002), p. 343.
Furthermore, contrary to the majority's assertion that chronological age at the time of the offense "will weigh relatively heavily at sentencing hearings," ante at 839 n. 35, a juvenile offender's chronological age is only one relevant consideration in determining whether the offender deserves a "sentence of life (and death) in prison." Miller, 567 U.S. at ___, 132 S.Ct. at 2468. Indeed, under Miller, a sentencer must consider the offender's chronological age, mental and emotional development, family and home environment, and potential for rehabilitation, along with the circumstances of the offense, which include the individual offender's role in the crime and whether familial and peer pressures may have affected the juvenile. Id. at ___, 132 S.Ct. at 2468. Simply stated, under Miller, a sentencer must "examine all these circumstances before concluding that life without any possibility of parole [is] the appropriate penalty." Id. at ___, 132 S.Ct. at 2469 (emphasis added). The majority, however, places "significant weight" on a juvenile's chronological age at the time of the offense. Ante at 839 n. 35. By stating that a juvenile who nears the age of majority at the time of the offense is "least likely" to be afforded "special leniency," ante at 839, that a juvenile "may even turn 18 during the proceedings related to the offense," ante at 839 n. 35, that a nonparolable life sentence is "increasingly likely to be permissible" to the extent the offender's age nears the age of majority, ante at 818 n. 9, and that age "may well constitute the single best factor" for determining culpability, ante at 839 n. 35, the majority makes generalizations that ignore Miller's multifaceted and holistic examination of the offender's individual characteristics.